Return to Video

Lecture 4-3 - Truth Functional Connectives Conjuction (16:11)

  • 0:04 - 0:09
    In the last lecture I explained what
    propositional connectives are, I described
  • 0:09 - 0:14
    a particular category of propositional
    connectives that we called truth
  • 0:14 - 0:19
    functional connectives, and I gave you an
    example of one truth functional
  • 0:19 - 0:25
    connective. And, another word, and in
    English isn't always used to mean a truth
  • 0:24 - 0:30
    functional connective, but sometimes it
    is. And one thing I'd like to point out
  • 0:30 - 0:36
    right now, is that there are other words
    in English that can be used to indicate
  • 0:36 - 0:43
    the very same truth functional connective
    that the word and is used to indicate. For
  • 0:43 - 0:48
    instance, think about the English words
    also, moreover, furthermore, and but. Now,
  • 0:48 - 0:56
    you might think the word and, and the word
    but" mean two very different things. If I
  • 0:56 - 1:02
    say Walter is poor and happy, that seems
    to mean something very different from
  • 1:02 - 1:09
    Walter is poor but happy. In particular,
    when I say Walter is poor but happy, I'm
  • 1:09 - 1:15
    suggesting that there is contrast between
    his poverty and his happiness. But when I
  • 1:15 - 1:21
    say Walter is poor and happy, I'm not
    suggesting any such contrast. Still,
  • 1:21 - 1:28
    whatever contrast there might be between
    his poverty and his happiness doesn't
  • 1:28 - 1:35
    effect the truth table for the truth
    functional connective but. Let's consider
  • 1:35 - 1:41
    when it would be true to say Walter is
    poor but happy. To show you what I mean,
  • 1:41 - 1:48
    about the words" but and, and," let's go
    back to the truth table for the truth
  • 1:47 - 1:53
    functional connective and. So remember, if
    you have two propositions, p1 and p2, and
  • 1:53 - 1:59
    you use the truth functional connective
    and to put them together to make another
  • 1:59 - 2:05
    proposition, the proposition p1 and p2.
    And now you wanna know when is that new
  • 2:05 - 2:11
    proposition, the proposition p1 and p2,
    when is that going to be true? Well, the
  • 2:11 - 2:20
    answer is it's going to be true only when
    p1 is true and p2 is true. In any other
  • 2:20 - 2:30
    scenario, the proposition p1 and p2 is
    gonna be false. Let's take an example so I
  • 2:30 - 2:40
    can illustrate. Let's suppose, for p1 we
    use the proposition Walter is poor, and
  • 2:40 - 2:51
    for p2 we use the proposition Walter is
    happy, then we use the truth functional
  • 2:51 - 2:55
    connective, and, to put those put two
    propositions together into a new
  • 2:55 - 3:09
    proposition and the new proposition is
    gonna be Walter is poor and happy. Okay.
  • 3:09 - 3:16
    Now, when it going to be true that Walter
    is poor and happy? Well, if it's true that
  • 3:16 - 3:22
    Walter is poor and it's also true that
    Walter is happy then its going to be true
  • 3:22 - 3:28
    that Walter is poor and happy. But, if
    it's false that Walter is poor, then it is
  • 3:28 - 3:34
    not going to be true that Walter is poor
    and happy. And if it's false that Walter
  • 3:34 - 3:40
    is happy, then it's not going to be true
    that Walter is poor and happy. So the
  • 3:40 - 3:47
    proposition Walter is poor and happy is
    gonna be true, only when Walter is poor is
  • 3:47 - 3:53
    true and Walter is happy is true. In any
    other possible scenario, the proposition
  • 3:53 - 4:01
    Walter is poor and happy will end up being
    false. So, lets compare that to the
  • 4:01 - 4:10
    proposition that we get by combining
    Walter is poor and Walter is happy with
  • 4:10 - 4:18
    the connective, but, Walter is poor but
    happy. Now, when is it gonna be true to
  • 4:18 - 4:24
    say Walter is poor but happy? Well, it's
    not gonna be true to say Walter is poor
  • 4:24 - 4:29
    but happy in any situation where it's
    false that Walter is poor. Right? If it's
  • 4:29 - 4:34
    false that Walter is poor, then it's also
    gonna be false that Walter is poor but
  • 4:34 - 4:39
    happy. It's also not gonna be true to say
    Walter is poor but happy in any situation
  • 4:39 - 4:45
    where it's false that Walter is happy. If
    it's false that Walter is happy, then it's
  • 4:45 - 4:51
    gonna be false that Walter is poor but
    happy. So when is it going to be true that
  • 4:51 - 4:56
    Walter is poor but happy? The only
    possible situation where it could be true
  • 4:56 - 5:02
    is the situation where it's true that
    Walter is poor and it's also true that
  • 5:02 - 5:07
    Walter is happy. Now, you might think,
    wait a second. When I say Walter is poor
  • 5:07 - 5:12
    but happy, I'm saying more than just that
    Walter is poor and that Walter is happy.
  • 5:12 - 5:18
    I'm also suggesting a contrast between his
    poverty and his happines. And maybe that
  • 5:18 - 5:25
    suggestion is misleading, maybe poor
    people are often happy. But notice, what
  • 5:25 - 5:32
    you say can be misleading even if it's
    true. For example, suppose someone comes
  • 5:32 - 5:39
    up to me with a car that's sputtering.
    They might say, do you know where there's
  • 5:39 - 5:45
    a gas station around here? I need to fill
    up this car with gas. And I might say,
  • 5:45 - 5:50
    there's a gas station just around the
    corner. Now, what I say might be true,
  • 5:50 - 5:55
    there might really be a gas station just
    around the corner even if I know that,
  • 5:55 - 6:01
    that gas station has been closed for three
    years and has no gas. So, what I say is
  • 6:01 - 6:06
    misleading because I've lead them to
    believe falsely, that they can get gas if
  • 6:06 - 6:11
    they can just get their car around the
    corner. But even though what I've said is
  • 6:11 - 6:17
    misleading, it's still true because there
    is a gas station around the corner, only a
  • 6:17 - 6:24
    closed one. So what you say can be true
    but misleading and I suggest that when you
  • 6:24 - 6:31
    say Walter is poor but happy. That can be
    true even if it's misleading to suggest
  • 6:31 - 6:36
    that poverty and happiness are somehow at
    odds with each other. I've just said that
  • 6:36 - 6:41
    the word but in English can be used to
    indicate the same truth functional
  • 6:41 - 6:46
    connective that the word and is sometimes
    used to indicate. And there are other
  • 6:46 - 6:51
    words in English that can be used to
    indicate that same truth functional
  • 6:51 - 6:56
    connective, also, furthermore, moreover,
    and sometimes we even use the word too,
  • 6:56 - 7:01
    too. But now I wanna introduce a term
    that's going to describe that truth
  • 7:01 - 7:07
    functional connective no matter what word
    in ordinary language we use to indicate
  • 7:07 - 7:14
    that connective. The term is conjunction.
    And the term conjunction, as I'm using it
  • 7:14 - 7:20
    here and as philosophers use it, is not
    the same term that grammarians use when
  • 7:20 - 7:27
    they talk about conjunctive terms like
    but, or, and, therefore. Here's something
  • 7:27 - 7:33
    that could help you understand what
    conjunctions in the grammarian sense are
  • 7:33 - 7:40
    like. All of those terms are conjunctions
    in the grammarian sense, but they're not
  • 7:40 - 7:46
    conjunctions in the philosopher's sense. A
    conjunction in the philosopher's sense is
  • 7:46 - 7:53
    just the truth functional connective that
    has this particular truth table. You can
  • 7:53 - 7:58
    use the conjunction to create a new
    proposition out of joining two other
  • 7:58 - 8:05
    propositions and that new proposition that
    you create using conjunction is gonna be
  • 8:05 - 8:11
    true, only when the other two propositions
    are true. In any other case, the new
  • 8:11 - 8:17
    proposition is going to be false, that's
    what a conjunction is. And we can use the
  • 8:17 - 8:23
    symbol ampersand, like that, in order to
    signify conjunction. Now that we know the
  • 8:23 - 8:29
    truth table for the conjunction, let's
    consider how we can use that truth table
  • 8:29 - 8:35
    to figure out when an argument that uses
    conjunction is valid. Consider the
  • 8:35 - 8:41
    argument Walter is poor but happy,
    therefore, Walter is happy. Is that
  • 8:41 - 8:46
    argument valid or invalid? Well, pretty
    obviously, that argument is valid. There's
  • 8:46 - 8:52
    no possible way for the premise to be true
    while the conclusion is false. But, can
  • 8:52 - 8:58
    you see why the argument is valid using
    the truth table for conjunction? You
  • 8:58 - 9:04
    should be able to in a situation in which
    the premise is true, Walter is poor but
  • 9:04 - 9:09
    happy, there are gonna have to be two
    other propositions that are true, namely
  • 9:09 - 9:15
    Walter is poor and Walter is happy. So, if
    its true that Walter is true but happy,
  • 9:15 - 9:21
    then its gonna have to be true that Walter
    is happy and that's why the argument is
  • 9:21 - 9:27
    valid. That's why there is no possible way
    for the premise to be true while the
  • 9:27 - 9:35
    conclusion is false. Let's consider some
    other arguments that involve conjunction.
  • 9:35 - 9:42
    Consider the argument Walter is poor,
    walter is happy, therefore, Walter is poor
  • 9:42 - 9:49
    and happy. Is that argument valid? Clearly
    it is. And again, you can use the truth
  • 9:49 - 9:54
    table for conjunctions to see why it's
    valid. In a situation where the first
  • 9:54 - 10:00
    premise Walter is poor is true, and in
    which the second premise Walter is happy
  • 10:00 - 10:07
    is true. In that situation, the conclusion
    Walter is poor and happy, is gonna have to
  • 10:07 - 10:13
    be true. So there's no possible way for
    the premises of that argument to both be
  • 10:13 - 10:19
    true while the conclusion is false and so
    that argument is also valid. Now notice,
  • 10:19 - 10:25
    just as we can combine two propositions
    with each other using conjunction, we can
  • 10:25 - 10:31
    then also combine the resulting
    proposition with another proposition using
  • 10:31 - 10:40
    conjunction. So, consider the proposition
    Walter is poor but happy and popular. That
  • 10:40 - 10:47
    proposition uses two conjunctions to
    combine three other propositions into a
  • 10:47 - 10:53
    single conjunctive proposition. To
    understand how that works, let's look at
  • 10:53 - 11:00
    the truth table for that. So when is it
    going to be true that Walter is poor but
  • 11:00 - 11:07
    happy and popular? When is that going to
    be true? Well, if it's false that Walter
  • 11:07 - 11:14
    is poor, then it's definitely not going to
    be true that Walter is poor but happy and
  • 11:14 - 11:22
    popular. So in all of these situations
    right down here, walter is poor but happy
  • 11:22 - 11:30
    and popular, is gonna to be false. If it's
    false that Walter is happy, then it's
  • 11:30 - 11:37
    definitely not going to be true that
    Walter is poor but happy and popular, cuz
  • 11:37 - 11:44
    he's not gonna be happy. So, in these
    situations right here where it's false
  • 11:44 - 11:51
    that Walter is happy, it's also gonna be
    false that Walter is poor but happy and
  • 11:51 - 11:58
    popular. And if it's false that Walter is
    popular, then of course, it's also gonna
  • 11:58 - 12:04
    be false that Walter is poor but happy and
    popular. So, in this situation right here,
  • 12:04 - 12:09
    it'll be false that Walter is poor but
    happy and popular. So, is it ever gonna be
  • 12:09 - 12:16
    true that Walter is poor but happy and
    popular? Yes. It'll be true just when it's
  • 12:16 - 12:23
    true that Walter is poor, it's true that
    Walter is happy, and it's true that Walter
  • 12:23 - 12:31
    is popular. That's the only situation when
    it's gonna be true that Walter is poor but
  • 12:31 - 12:37
    happy and popular. In general, this is the
    kind of truth table that we get when we
  • 12:37 - 12:43
    combine three propositions using
    conjunction. So now, considered how we can
  • 12:43 - 12:49
    use the truth table for conjunctions of
    three propositions to figure out whether
  • 12:49 - 12:54
    certain deductive arguments are valid or
    not. So consider the following deductive
  • 12:54 - 13:00
    argument. From the premises Paris is the
    capital of France, Jakarta is the capital
  • 13:00 - 13:05
    of Indonesia, and Washington DC is the
    capital of the United States. Let's
  • 13:05 - 13:10
    conclude Paris is the capital of France,
    and Jakarta is the capital of Indonesia,
  • 13:10 - 13:16
    and Washington D.C. is the capitol of the
    United States. Valid or not? Well,
  • 13:16 - 13:24
    clearly, that argument is valid and the
    truth table shows us why. The conclusion
  • 13:24 - 13:28
    Paris is the capital of France, and
    Jakarta is the capital of Indonesia, and
  • 13:28 - 13:34
    Wash ington D.C. is the capital of the
    United States is true just when it's true
  • 13:34 - 13:39
    that Paris is the capital of France, and
    it's also true that Jakarta is the capital
  • 13:39 - 13:44
    of Indonesia, and it's also true that
    Washington D.C. is the capital of the
  • 13:44 - 13:49
    United States. So whenever the premises
    are true, the conclusion is also true, and
  • 13:49 - 13:54
    that's why that argument is valid. The
    truth table explains why the argument is
  • 13:54 - 14:01
    valid. Now consider a different one. From
    the premise Mick Jagger is a singer, a
  • 14:01 - 14:08
    man, and a septuagenarian. We could draw
    the conclusion Mick Jagger is a
  • 14:08 - 14:14
    septuagenarian. Now is that argument
    valid? Yes, it is and the truth table for
  • 14:14 - 14:20
    conjunction explains why it's valid. Think
    about the situation in which it's true
  • 14:20 - 14:26
    that Mick Jagger is a man, a singer, and a
    septuagenarian. The only situation in
  • 14:26 - 14:32
    which that's true is the situation in
    which it's true that Mick Jagger is a man,
  • 14:32 - 14:37
    it's true that Mick Jagger is a singer,
    and it's true that Mick Jagger is a
  • 14:37 - 14:43
    septuagenarian. But that means that if the
    premises is true, then the conclusion has
  • 14:43 - 14:49
    got to be true. The premise is only true
    in a situation in which the conclusion is
  • 14:49 - 14:54
    true and so that argument has got to be
    valid and the truth table for conjunction
  • 14:54 - 15:00
    explains why. I have said that conjunction
    can be used to connect two other
  • 15:00 - 15:05
    propositions into a new proposition. And
    conjunction can also be used to connect
  • 15:05 - 15:10
    three other propositions into a new
    proposition. But there's no limit to the
  • 15:10 - 15:14
    number of propositions that can be
    connected using the truth functional
  • 15:15 - 15:21
    connective conjunction, or as we could
    say, there's no limit to the number of
  • 15:21 - 15:27
    propositions that can be conjoined. You
    can conjoin four propositions, five
  • 15:27 - 15:33
    propositions, or however many you like,
    and notice that there's a pattern to the
  • 15:33 - 15:38
    truth tables for all of these
    conjunctions. In every case, the conjoined
  • 15:38 - 15:45
    proposition is gonna be true only when all
    of the propositions that are conjoined in
  • 15:45 - 15:50
    it are true. Now, I'ld like you to take
    several minutes and look at the following
  • 15:50 - 15:56
    truth tables, and identify which of these
    truth tables are truth tables for
  • 15:56 - 16:01
    conjunction and which of them are not.
    Well, that's it for our discussion of
  • 16:01 - 16:05
    conjunction and reasoning with
    conjunctions. In the next lecture we'll
  • 16:05 - 16:11
    introduce the topic of disjunction and
    reasoning with disjunctions. See you next
Title:
Lecture 4-3 - Truth Functional Connectives Conjuction (16:11)
Video Language:
Chinese, Simplified (Singaporean)

English subtitles

Revisions