Return to Video

What are numbers? | Kit Fine | TEDxNewYork

  • 0:17 - 0:20
    Numbers are strange.
  • 0:21 - 0:23
    They are not physical objects.
  • 0:23 - 0:29
    No one has bumped into the number two
    or tripped over the number three;
  • 0:29 - 0:31
    not even your crazy math professor.
  • 0:32 - 0:36
    They are not mental objects either.
  • 0:36 - 0:39
    The thought of your beloved
    isn't your beloved
  • 0:39 - 0:42
    no matter how much
    you might want it to be.
  • 0:42 - 0:46
    And no more is the thought
    of the number three, the number three.
  • 0:47 - 0:51
    Nor do numbers exist in space or time.
  • 0:51 - 0:55
    You don't expect to find the number three
    in the kitchen cupboard,
  • 0:55 - 0:57
    and you don't need to worry
  • 0:57 - 1:03
    that numbers once didn't exist
    or might one day cease to exist.
  • 1:03 - 1:07
    But even though numbers
    are far removed
  • 1:07 - 1:10
    from the familiar world
    of thoughts and things,
  • 1:11 - 1:18
    they're intimately connected to that world
    because we do things with numbers.
  • 1:18 - 1:22
    We count with them, we measure with them,
  • 1:22 - 1:26
    we formulate
    our scientific theories with them.
  • 1:27 - 1:31
    So this makes it
    all the stranger what they are.
  • 1:31 - 1:36
    How can they be so far removed
    from the familiar world
  • 1:36 - 1:39
    and yet so intimately connected to it?
  • 1:40 - 1:46
    In this talk I want to consider
    three views about the nature of number
  • 1:46 - 1:50
    that were developed
    by mathematicians and philosophers
  • 1:50 - 1:56
    around the end of the 19th century
    and the beginning of the 20th century.
  • 1:57 - 2:00
    All of these views presuppose
    that strictly speaking
  • 2:00 - 2:05
    what we count are not things,
    but sets of things.
  • 2:05 - 2:12
    A set is just many things, any things
    you like, considered as one.
  • 2:12 - 2:18
    So for example, we have the set
    of beer bottles that you drank last night.
  • 2:20 - 2:23
    The bottles are put in these braces
    to indicate that the six bottles
  • 2:23 - 2:26
    are being considered as one object.
  • 2:26 - 2:32
    Then we have the set consisting
    of your two favorite pets, Fido and Felix.
  • 2:33 - 2:38
    Or we have a set consisting
    of all the natural numbers,
  • 2:38 - 2:40
    so they're put together
    in this very big set:
  • 2:40 - 2:43
    0, 1, 2, 3, 4 and so on.
  • 2:44 - 2:49
    And so what we do when we count
    is associate a number with a set.
  • 2:49 - 2:52
    In the case of the beer bottles,
    the number six,
  • 2:52 - 2:56
    assuming you're not too drunk
    to count them.
  • 2:57 - 3:00
    In the case of your pets, the number two.
  • 3:00 - 3:05
    And in the case of the natural numbers,
    when we put them into one big set,
  • 3:05 - 3:07
    is going to be some infinite number.
  • 3:08 - 3:12
    The first view I want to consider
    about the nature of numbers
  • 3:12 - 3:17
    was developed independently
    by two great philosopher mathematicians,
  • 3:17 - 3:20
    Gottlob Frege and Bertrand Russell.
  • 3:20 - 3:23
    These two individuals
    were very different from one another.
  • 3:24 - 3:27
    Russell came from the English aristocracy;
  • 3:27 - 3:30
    Frege from the comfortable
    German middle class.
  • 3:31 - 3:34
    Russell was a crusading liberal;
  • 3:35 - 3:38
    Frege, I'm sorry to say, was a proto-Nazi.
  • 3:39 - 3:45
    Russell had four wives,
    and innumerable mistresses;
  • 3:45 - 3:47
    Frege had a single wife,
  • 3:47 - 3:53
    and as far as I know,
    enjoyed a happy, staid marital existence.
  • 3:53 - 3:56
    But despite these differences,
  • 3:56 - 3:59
    they had more or less the same view
    about the nature of number.
  • 3:59 - 4:01
    So what was it?
  • 4:01 - 4:04
    Well let's take the number two
    as an example.
  • 4:04 - 4:09
    Two can be used to number
    any two-membered set or pair.
  • 4:09 - 4:16
    So it can be used to number the set
    whose members are Frege and Russell.
  • 4:16 - 4:18
    Or it can be used to number the set
  • 4:18 - 4:22
    consisting of your favorite pets,
    Fido and Felix.
  • 4:23 - 4:26
    Or it can be used to number
  • 4:26 - 4:29
    Dickens' famous two cities,
    London and Paris.
  • 4:29 - 4:32
    I insisted that London
    be placed first there.
  • 4:32 - 4:34
    (Laughter)
  • 4:35 - 4:42
    Now the idea of Russell and Frege was to
    put all of these pairs into one big set.
  • 4:43 - 4:47
    We pile them all into one big set,
    and that would be the number two.
  • 4:47 - 4:50
    So the number two
    would be a set of sets,
  • 4:50 - 4:55
    and these sets would just be all the pairs
    that could be counted by the number two.
  • 4:55 - 4:58
    Similarly, for all other numbers,
  • 4:58 - 5:00
    the number three
    would be the set of all triples,
  • 5:00 - 5:04
    the number four the set
    of all quadruples, and so on.
  • 5:04 - 5:07
    A simple and beautiful theory.
  • 5:08 - 5:12
    Unfortunately, it led to contradiction.
  • 5:13 - 5:16
    I can't give a demonstration
    of the contradiction here,
  • 5:16 - 5:19
    but I can give you a feel
    for how it arose.
  • 5:20 - 5:25
    You'll recall that the number two
    was the set of all pairs,
  • 5:25 - 5:27
    all pairs of whatever.
  • 5:27 - 5:33
    So in particular, it would include pairs
    that themselves contain the number two.
  • 5:34 - 5:36
    So let's look at the particular such pair,
  • 5:36 - 5:39
    the pair consisting of the number two
    and the number one.
  • 5:42 - 5:46
    Then that pair, the pair {1, 2},
    would itself be inside the number two.
  • 5:46 - 5:49
    So the number two would contain itself,
  • 5:50 - 5:53
    and that looks as if it's impossible.
  • 5:53 - 5:55
    So here's an analogy:
  • 5:55 - 6:00
    imagine a very hungry serpent
    that tries to eat its own tail.
  • 6:00 - 6:03
    Now, it could succeed in doing this
  • 6:03 - 6:07
    - this is the best we could do
    by way of illustration -
  • 6:07 - 6:09
    This is gross, but still possible.
  • 6:09 - 6:11
    (Laughter)
  • 6:11 - 6:14
    But imagine now
    that the serpent is so ravenous
  • 6:14 - 6:18
    that it attempts to eat itself
    in its entirety.
  • 6:19 - 6:21
    That's not even possible
  • 6:21 - 6:26
    because then, the serpent's stomach
    would have to be inside its stomach.
  • 6:26 - 6:29
    And that's what happens
    with the number two.
  • 6:29 - 6:35
    The number two, as you see,
    has itself inside of its very own stomach.
  • 6:36 - 6:38
    What was to be done?
  • 6:39 - 6:44
    The mathematician John von Neumann
    came up with a brilliant solution;
  • 6:45 - 6:48
    von Neumann was perhaps
    one of the most versatile mathematicians
  • 6:48 - 6:50
    who ever existed.
  • 6:50 - 6:54
    He helped invent game theory
    and the modern computer.
  • 6:55 - 6:58
    He was a prodigy
  • 6:58 - 7:01
    and had the most amazing
    computational skills.
  • 7:01 - 7:05
    So what was his solution?
  • 7:05 - 7:06
    There he is.
  • 7:06 - 7:07
    He said: "Well look,
  • 7:07 - 7:13
    rather than take the number two
    to be the set of all pairs,
  • 7:13 - 7:16
    take it to be a particular pair."
  • 7:16 - 7:19
    Well, which pair would it be?
  • 7:19 - 7:24
    He suggested that the number two
    should be the set of its predecessors.
  • 7:24 - 7:29
    Two has two predecessors, zero and one.
  • 7:29 - 7:35
    We take two to be the set
    whose members are zero and one.
  • 7:35 - 7:38
    But we still have numbers;
    we have zero and one.
  • 7:38 - 7:43
    Well, zero is the set of its predecessors.
  • 7:43 - 7:46
    Zero has no predecessors,
    so it's what's called the 'null set,'
  • 7:46 - 7:48
    the set without any members.
  • 7:48 - 7:53
    And one has one predecessor,
    which is zero.
  • 7:53 - 7:57
    So one is the set
    whose sole member is zero.
  • 7:57 - 8:02
    So there we have two defined,
    one defined and zero defined.
  • 8:02 - 8:06
    If we put these definitions
    together, we get the set.
  • 8:06 - 8:10
    The number two is the set
    whose two members are the null set,
  • 8:10 - 8:12
    which is the number zero,
  • 8:12 - 8:16
    and the set whose sole member
    is the null set, which is the number one.
  • 8:17 - 8:22
    So that's according to von Neumann
    what the number two is;
  • 8:22 - 8:24
    it's sets all the way down
  • 8:25 - 8:27
    - sets, not turtles -
  • 8:27 - 8:30
    And you actually hit rock bottom, too.
  • 8:31 - 8:34
    And similarly for all other numbers,
  • 8:34 - 8:37
    the number three would be
    an even more complicated thing, and so on.
  • 8:38 - 8:43
    Remember, the Frege-Russell view
    gave birth to monsters.
  • 8:43 - 8:46
    Here, we no longer have a monster;
  • 8:46 - 8:48
    the monster has turned into an angel,
  • 8:48 - 8:51
    because although the number two
    contains other numbers,
  • 8:51 - 8:53
    it doesn't contain itself.
  • 8:54 - 8:58
    The monster is always eating
    a smaller monster, so to speak.
  • 8:59 - 9:01
    It doesn't get in the way of itself.
  • 9:01 - 9:06
    This view is generally accepted
    by philosophers and mathematicians today,
  • 9:06 - 9:08
    but it also has its difficulties.
  • 9:09 - 9:11
    One difficulty that especially bothers me
  • 9:11 - 9:14
    is there's nothing special
    about the number two.
  • 9:14 - 9:19
    We want the number two
    to be what is common to all pairs,
  • 9:20 - 9:25
    but von Neumann's number two
    is just one pair among many,
  • 9:25 - 9:27
    and there's no special way
  • 9:27 - 9:31
    in which that pair is
    what's common to all pairs.
  • 9:32 - 9:34
    So it doesn't make
    the number two special anyway;
  • 9:34 - 9:37
    it's just one pair among many.
  • 9:37 - 9:43
    We come now to the final view,
    and the one I like most of all.
  • 9:45 - 9:50
    It's a view that's generally
    dismissed or ignored
  • 9:50 - 9:53
    by philosophers
    and mathematicians of today.
  • 9:53 - 9:58
    It was developed by Georg Cantor
    in the late 19th century.
  • 9:59 - 10:05
    Cantor was a multi-talented individual,
  • 10:05 - 10:08
    a brilliant violinist
  • 10:11 - 10:16
    with wide-ranging interests
    ranging from religion to literature.
  • 10:17 - 10:21
    But he's best known
    for his theory of infinite number.
  • 10:22 - 10:26
    Cantor wanted to count
    not only finite collections
  • 10:26 - 10:29
    - I know there are a lot of people here,
    but it's still a finite number -
  • 10:29 - 10:33
    so not just the finite collections,
    like the number of people here,
  • 10:33 - 10:36
    or the number of stars in the Milky Way,
  • 10:36 - 10:39
    he also wanted
    to count infinite collections,
  • 10:39 - 10:44
    like the collection of all natural numbers
    or the collection of all points in space.
  • 10:45 - 10:50
    And to this end, he attempted
    to develop a general theory of number.
  • 10:51 - 10:53
    So what was his view?
  • 10:53 - 10:56
    Again, let's consider the number two.
  • 10:56 - 11:00
    Let's take two objects, Fido and Felix.
  • 11:00 - 11:02
    Now Cantor said:
  • 11:02 - 11:08
    "Look, let's deprive these two objects
    of all of their individuating features
  • 11:08 - 11:12
    beyond their being distinct
    from one another."
  • 11:12 - 11:14
    So we remove their fur,
  • 11:14 - 11:19
    we remove their flesh and blood,
  • 11:19 - 11:22
    until we're simply left
    with two bare objects
  • 11:22 - 11:25
    - what he called units
    without any differentiating features.
  • 11:25 - 11:28
    I hope there are no animal lovers
    amongst you.
  • 11:28 - 11:33
    But anyway, this is what happens to pets
    when Cantor gets hold of them.
  • 11:34 - 11:36
    So what are these units?
  • 11:36 - 11:40
    Well, take the two dollars
    in your bank account
  • 11:40 - 11:43
    - I hope you still have two dollars left
    after paying the admission fee.
  • 11:43 - 11:47
    These two dollars
    aren't any particular dollars,
  • 11:47 - 11:50
    but when you go to the ATM machine,
  • 11:50 - 11:53
    you can redeem them
    for two particular dollars.
  • 11:53 - 11:55
    So they aren't those particular dollars,
  • 11:55 - 11:58
    but they can be redeemed
    for any two particular dollars.
  • 11:58 - 12:00
    This is what Cantor's units are like.
  • 12:00 - 12:04
    But when you go to the Cantorian
    ATM machine to redeem your units,
  • 12:04 - 12:07
    you get back any two objects or whatever.
  • 12:07 - 12:09
    It's the ultimate lucky dip.
  • 12:10 - 12:12
    Cantor's idea was this:
  • 12:12 - 12:17
    we take the number two
    to be the set of these two units.
  • 12:17 - 12:19
    So we take these two units,
  • 12:19 - 12:22
    which could be derived
    from any two objects,
  • 12:22 - 12:27
    and the number two
    is the set of those two units.
  • 12:27 - 12:29
    And similarly, for all other numbers;
  • 12:29 - 12:31
    the number three
    would be the set of three units,
  • 12:31 - 12:34
    and so on and so forth.
  • 12:34 - 12:37
    So we have three views on the table.
  • 12:37 - 12:39
    The Frege-Russell view
  • 12:39 - 12:42
    according to which the number two
    is the set of all pairs;
  • 12:42 - 12:44
    the view of von Neumann,
  • 12:44 - 12:48
    according to which the number two
    is the set whose members are zero and one;
  • 12:48 - 12:52
    and the Cantorian view,
  • 12:52 - 12:56
    according to which two
    is the set of two units.
  • 12:56 - 13:02
    The Frege-Russell view breeds
    monsters, so we can't have it.
  • 13:03 - 13:06
    The von Neumann view
    doesn't properly account
  • 13:06 - 13:10
    for why the number two
    is common to all pairs.
  • 13:11 - 13:15
    The Cantorian view suffers
    from neither of those difficulties.
  • 13:15 - 13:19
    It doesn't breed monsters because
    the number two only contains units;
  • 13:19 - 13:22
    it doesn't itself contain the number two.
  • 13:22 - 13:25
    And it's, in an obvious sense,
    common to all pairs,
  • 13:25 - 13:28
    because it's derived
    by this process of abstraction,
  • 13:28 - 13:31
    or stripping away, from each pair.
  • 13:33 - 13:37
    So thanks to Cantor,
    we now know what numbers are.
  • 13:38 - 13:39
    Thank you.
  • 13:39 - 13:40
    (Applause)
Title:
What are numbers? | Kit Fine | TEDxNewYork
Description:

This talk was given at a local TEDx event, produced independently of the TED conferences.
Numbers are neither physical objects nor mental ones. They don't exist in space or time, and yet, we are so intimately connected to them.
In this captivating talk, Kit Fine considers three views about the nature of numbers.

more » « less
Video Language:
English
Team:
closed TED
Project:
TEDxTalks
Duration:
13:44

English subtitles

Revisions