1 00:00:02,660 --> 00:00:08,096 The next question has probably been bothering you ever since very early on in 2 00:00:08,096 --> 00:00:13,874 the previous lecture. Namely, if valid arguments can have false premises, then 3 00:00:13,874 --> 00:00:19,154 what good are they? Sure, there's this technical logician's notion of a valid 4 00:00:19,154 --> 00:00:24,919 argument, but why should we care whether arguments are valid if valid arguments can 5 00:00:24,919 --> 00:00:30,824 be really bad? Validity might be necessary for an argument to be good or at least for 6 00:00:30,824 --> 00:00:35,965 a deductive argument to be good because remember, there are also inductive 7 00:00:35,965 --> 00:00:42,407 arguments. But even though it's necessary, it's not enough. You can have a horrible 8 00:00:42,407 --> 00:00:48,260 argument but still valid. Well, the great thing about validity is that when you add 9 00:00:48,260 --> 00:00:54,042 true premises to a valid argument, then you get something that really is valuable, 10 00:00:54,042 --> 00:00:58,967 which we're going to call a sound argument. Because if you know that the 11 00:00:58,967 --> 00:01:04,820 premises are true and you also know that it's not possible for the premises to be 12 00:01:04,820 --> 00:01:10,790 true and the conclusion, false, then, you know, the conclusion must be true. So, in 13 00:01:10,790 --> 00:01:16,954 a sound argument, the conclusion has to be true. And that is what makes it valuable 14 00:01:16,954 --> 00:01:23,193 cuz if we can get a deductive argument to be sound, then you really got something. 15 00:01:23,193 --> 00:01:28,981 What you've got is a true conclusion. Officially then, a sound argument is one 16 00:01:28,981 --> 00:01:35,167 where the premises are true and the argument is valid. And we've got the same 17 00:01:35,167 --> 00:01:40,574 combinations of truth and falsity as possibilities that we had in valid 18 00:01:40,574 --> 00:01:46,431 arguments. You can have both premises and conclusion are true and then, if it's 19 00:01:46,431 --> 00:01:52,289 valid, the argument is sound and if it's not valid, it's not. Or you can have the 20 00:01:52,289 --> 00:01:58,147 premises are true and the conclusions false and then, it can't be valid. But if 21 00:01:58,147 --> 00:02:04,460 it's invalid, it's not sound. We can have the premises are false and the conclusions 22 00:02:04,694 --> 00:02:10,776 true. And then if it's valid, it's not sound and if it's invalid, it's not sound. 23 00:02:10,776 --> 00:02:17,014 Or we can have both the premises and the conclusion are false, and then, it's not 24 00:02:17,014 --> 00:02:22,784 going to be sound whether it's valid or not. So, the only combination, where it 25 00:02:22,784 --> 00:02:28,944 sound is when the premises are true and the argument is valid and, in that case, 26 00:02:28,944 --> 00:02:34,517 you know that the conclusion is true. What about lack of soundness? Well, there are 27 00:02:34,517 --> 00:02:39,754 two ways an argument yjay fail to be sound, namely, either the argument can be 28 00:02:39,754 --> 00:02:44,785 invalid or one of its premises can be false. So, it's a lot easier for an 29 00:02:44,785 --> 00:02:50,294 argument to be unsound. And we know that a deductive argument tries to be valid and, 30 00:02:50,294 --> 00:02:55,592 of course, it wants its premises to be true so a deductive argument is trying to 31 00:02:55,592 --> 00:03:00,582 be sound. And when it fails to be sound, it's not going to be any good. And the 32 00:03:00,582 --> 00:03:06,437 next question is how can you know? If you don't know whether the premises are true, 33 00:03:06,437 --> 00:03:11,059 you're not going to know whether the arguments sound. Well, not quite, because 34 00:03:11,059 --> 00:03:15,743 if you, if the argument's valid and you know it's valid, then you don't know 35 00:03:15,743 --> 00:03:20,552 whether it's sound unless you know the premises are true. But if you that the 36 00:03:20,552 --> 00:03:25,237 argument is invalid, you already know it's unsound, even if you don't know whether 37 00:03:25,237 --> 00:03:30,046 the premises are true. So, if you think about it, that shows why you want to be 38 00:03:30,046 --> 00:03:34,869 able to test for validity. Because if you can show the argument's invalid, then 39 00:03:34,869 --> 00:03:39,669 you're going to be able to, well, I know it's unsound, regardless of what you think 40 00:03:39,669 --> 00:03:44,407 about whether the premises are true or not. So, there's going to be some value to 41 00:03:44,407 --> 00:03:49,084 validity, namely, if you can show it's invalid, you're going to show it's unsound 42 00:03:49,084 --> 00:03:54,504 and that means that the deductive argument didn't get what it wanted. So, validity is 43 00:03:54,504 --> 00:04:00,535 going to be necessary for soundness and soundness is going to be important because 44 00:04:00,535 --> 00:04:06,879 it guarantees the truth of the conclusion, and then, validity derives its value from 45 00:04:06,879 --> 00:04:12,814 the fact that if it's not valid, it's not sound. Okay. Now, there's a more to say 46 00:04:12,814 --> 00:04:17,227 about validity. And we'll say a lot more about validity when we get to a formal 47 00:04:17,669 --> 00:04:22,587 logic in the second part of this course. But for now, we're just going to stick 48 00:04:22,587 --> 00:04:27,252 with this pretty intuitive notion of validity and see how we can use this 49 00:04:27,252 --> 00:04:30,027 notion of validity to reconstruct arguments.