0:00:02.660,0:00:08.096 The next question has probably been[br]bothering you ever since very early on in 0:00:08.096,0:00:13.874 the previous lecture. Namely, if valid[br]arguments can have false premises, then 0:00:13.874,0:00:19.154 what good are they? Sure, there's this[br]technical logician's notion of a valid 0:00:19.154,0:00:24.919 argument, but why should we care whether[br]arguments are valid if valid arguments can 0:00:24.919,0:00:30.824 be really bad? Validity might be necessary[br]for an argument to be good or at least for 0:00:30.824,0:00:35.965 a deductive argument to be good because[br]remember, there are also inductive 0:00:35.965,0:00:42.407 arguments. But even though it's necessary,[br]it's not enough. You can have a horrible 0:00:42.407,0:00:48.260 argument but still valid. Well, the great[br]thing about validity is that when you add 0:00:48.260,0:00:54.042 true premises to a valid argument, then[br]you get something that really is valuable, 0:00:54.042,0:00:58.967 which we're going to call a sound[br]argument. Because if you know that the 0:00:58.967,0:01:04.820 premises are true and you also know that[br]it's not possible for the premises to be 0:01:04.820,0:01:10.790 true and the conclusion, false, then, you[br]know, the conclusion must be true. So, in 0:01:10.790,0:01:16.954 a sound argument, the conclusion has to be[br]true. And that is what makes it valuable 0:01:16.954,0:01:23.193 cuz if we can get a deductive argument to[br]be sound, then you really got something. 0:01:23.193,0:01:28.981 What you've got is a true conclusion.[br]Officially then, a sound argument is one 0:01:28.981,0:01:35.167 where the premises are true and the[br]argument is valid. And we've got the same 0:01:35.167,0:01:40.574 combinations of truth and falsity as[br]possibilities that we had in valid 0:01:40.574,0:01:46.431 arguments. You can have both premises and[br]conclusion are true and then, if it's 0:01:46.431,0:01:52.289 valid, the argument is sound and if it's[br]not valid, it's not. Or you can have the 0:01:52.289,0:01:58.147 premises are true and the conclusions[br]false and then, it can't be valid. But if 0:01:58.147,0:02:04.460 it's invalid, it's not sound. We can have[br]the premises are false and the conclusions 0:02:04.694,0:02:10.776 true. And then if it's valid, it's not[br]sound and if it's invalid, it's not sound. 0:02:10.776,0:02:17.014 Or we can have both the premises and the[br]conclusion are false, and then, it's not 0:02:17.014,0:02:22.784 going to be sound whether it's valid or[br]not. So, the only combination, where it 0:02:22.784,0:02:28.944 sound is when the premises are true and[br]the argument is valid and, in that case, 0:02:28.944,0:02:34.517 you know that the conclusion is true. What[br]about lack of soundness? Well, there are 0:02:34.517,0:02:39.754 two ways an argument yjay fail to be[br]sound, namely, either the argument can be 0:02:39.754,0:02:44.785 invalid or one of its premises can be[br]false. So, it's a lot easier for an 0:02:44.785,0:02:50.294 argument to be unsound. And we know that a[br]deductive argument tries to be valid and, 0:02:50.294,0:02:55.592 of course, it wants its premises to be[br]true so a deductive argument is trying to 0:02:55.592,0:03:00.582 be sound. And when it fails to be sound,[br]it's not going to be any good. And the 0:03:00.582,0:03:06.437 next question is how can you know? If you[br]don't know whether the premises are true, 0:03:06.437,0:03:11.059 you're not going to know whether the[br]arguments sound. Well, not quite, because 0:03:11.059,0:03:15.743 if you, if the argument's valid and you[br]know it's valid, then you don't know 0:03:15.743,0:03:20.552 whether it's sound unless you know the[br]premises are true. But if you that the 0:03:20.552,0:03:25.237 argument is invalid, you already know it's[br]unsound, even if you don't know whether 0:03:25.237,0:03:30.046 the premises are true. So, if you think[br]about it, that shows why you want to be 0:03:30.046,0:03:34.869 able to test for validity. Because if you[br]can show the argument's invalid, then 0:03:34.869,0:03:39.669 you're going to be able to, well, I know[br]it's unsound, regardless of what you think 0:03:39.669,0:03:44.407 about whether the premises are true or[br]not. So, there's going to be some value to 0:03:44.407,0:03:49.084 validity, namely, if you can show it's[br]invalid, you're going to show it's unsound 0:03:49.084,0:03:54.504 and that means that the deductive argument[br]didn't get what it wanted. So, validity is 0:03:54.504,0:04:00.535 going to be necessary for soundness and[br]soundness is going to be important because 0:04:00.535,0:04:06.879 it guarantees the truth of the conclusion,[br]and then, validity derives its value from 0:04:06.879,0:04:12.814 the fact that if it's not valid, it's not[br]sound. Okay. Now, there's a more to say 0:04:12.814,0:04:17.227 about validity. And we'll say a lot more[br]about validity when we get to a formal 0:04:17.669,0:04:22.587 logic in the second part of this course.[br]But for now, we're just going to stick 0:04:22.587,0:04:27.252 with this pretty intuitive notion of[br]validity and see how we can use this 0:04:27.252,0:04:30.027 notion of validity to reconstruct[br]arguments.