Return to Video

Lecture 3-6 - Fill in Gaps and Conclude

  • 0:03 - 0:11
    It's been a long and winding road as the
    Beatles used to say, but we're finally at
  • 0:11 - 0:17
    the last stages of reconstructing
    arguments. We've looked at stage one,
  • 0:17 - 0:24
    which is close analysis. Stage two which
    is get down to basics. Stage three which
  • 0:24 - 0:31
    is sharpen edges, stage four is organize
    parts, and we are doing stage five which
  • 0:31 - 0:38
    is fill in gaps and we'll also get to
    stage six which is conclude. Stage five
  • 0:38 - 0:43
    really consists of four separate steps.
    First we need to assess the argument for
  • 0:43 - 0:48
    validity. Then we need to add suppressed
    premises. Enough of them to make it valid.
  • 0:48 - 0:53
    Then we need to assess those suppressed
    premises for truth or falsehood. And then
  • 0:53 - 0:58
    we need to qualify the suppressed premises
    in order to make them true. The whole goal
  • 0:58 - 1:04
    is to make the suppressed premises both
    plausible for their truth, and enough to
  • 1:04 - 1:09
    make the argument valid. So, these steps
    within the stage really do work in tandem
  • 1:09 - 1:14
    together to try and make the argument
    good. We already learned how to assess
  • 1:14 - 1:19
    validity. You simply ask, "Is it possible
    for the premises to be true and the
  • 1:19 - 1:24
    conclusion false, and if so, the argument
    is not valid and if not, the argument is
  • 1:24 - 1:29
    valid." And the way you figure out whether
    it's possible is you try to tell a story
  • 1:29 - 1:33
    or describe a situation and if you can
    describe a coherent situation where the
  • 1:33 - 1:38
    premises are true and the conclusion is
    false, then that show that the argument is
  • 1:38 - 1:43
    not really valid. The main topic for today
    is, what do you do when you assess the
  • 1:43 - 1:48
    argument for validity and you find out
    it's not valid?" And the answer is, you
  • 1:48 - 1:54
    add suppressed premises, enough of them to
    make the argument valid. But that might
  • 1:54 - 1:59
    seem like cheating. I mean, you start with
    an argument that's no good, it's not
  • 1:59 - 2:04
    valid, and then you just throw in some
    extra premises in order to make it valid.
  • 2:04 - 2:09
    Why is it that's just distorting the
    argument and making up something that
  • 2:09 - 2:14
    wasn't there? The answer is that it's not
    really bad. And if it were bad, we'd all
  • 2:14 - 2:19
    be in bad shape because in everyday life,
    people always take things for granted.
  • 2:19 - 2:24
    They make assumptions. We do it too, and
    if we didn't, boy, our arguments would be
  • 2:24 - 2:29
    really long and boring. So there's
    something to be said in favor of
  • 2:29 - 2:34
    suppressing premises, at least, the
    obvious ones that people really do take
  • 2:34 - 2:40
    for granted. But we can also get tricked.
    People can suppress premises that really
  • 2:40 - 2:45
    are questionable, and they just don't want
    us to see that they're making that
  • 2:45 - 2:51
    assumption. So, it's useful to fill out
    the argument with suppressed premises to
  • 2:51 - 2:56
    make sure it really is valid, because that
    brings those assumptions out in the open,
  • 2:56 - 3:01
    where we can assess whether or not they're
    true or false. Another reason to fill in
  • 3:01 - 3:06
    suppressed premises is to understand the
    argument better. Because if people
  • 3:06 - 3:11
    suppress premises, then they're showing us
    some of their footprints along the path.
  • 3:11 - 3:16
    But if we really want to know the full
    path that their reasoning followed, we've
  • 3:16 - 3:21
    got to see every single footprint. So, the
    goal of bringing up the suppressed
  • 3:21 - 3:26
    premises is to let us trace exactly where
    the reasoning is from one step to another.
  • 3:26 - 3:31
    So there are two goals: One is to trace
    the full path every step and the other
  • 3:31 - 3:36
    goal is to see if there are any miss-steps
    or they are trying to hid something from
  • 3:36 - 3:41
    us by getting rid of one of their
    footsteps, so that's the point of bringing
  • 3:41 - 3:46
    up suppressed premises. To accomplish
    these goals is tricky. You have to find
  • 3:46 - 3:51
    suppressed premises that are just strong
    enough to make the argument valid but not
  • 3:51 - 3:57
    so strong that there gonna be implausible.
    Cuz you don't wanna ascribe all kinds of
  • 3:57 - 4:01
    suppressed premises to the person that
    they didn't really believe, and they
  • 4:01 - 4:07
    didn't really need for their argument. So
    it's kind of like Goldilocks and the Three
  • 4:07 - 4:12
    Bears. You want suppressed premises to be
    not too hot and not too cold, but just
  • 4:12 - 4:18
    right. Here's an example from a previous
    lecture. My wife always gives me either a
  • 4:18 - 4:24
    sweater or a board game. This box does not
    contain a sweater because it rattles when
  • 4:24 - 4:30
    it's shaken so this time she must have
    given me a board game. We put this in
  • 4:30 - 4:36
    standard form this way. First premise:
    This box rattles wh en I shake it and that
  • 4:36 - 4:43
    shows you it doesn't contain a sweater.
    Third, she always gives me either a
  • 4:43 - 4:49
    sweater or a board game. Conclusion, this
    time she must have given me a board game.
  • 4:50 - 4:57
    Now the first step in this argument is,
    this box rattles when I shake it. And the
  • 4:57 - 5:03
    conclusion there is it doesn't contain a
    sweater. That's the part of the argument
  • 5:03 - 5:09
    we want to focus on here and ask whether
    that argument is valid. The argument is
  • 5:09 - 5:14
    not valid, because it's possible for the
    premise to be true and the conclusion
  • 5:14 - 5:20
    false. How can that happen? Well, my wife
    might be fooling me. She might know that I
  • 5:20 - 5:25
    expect either a sweater or a board game,
    so she puts a sweater in the box. And then
  • 5:25 - 5:30
    she puts little rocks around the outside
    so when I shake it, I'll hear something.
  • 5:30 - 5:35
    So that's possible, and that shows that
    the argument's not valid. Well, how can we
  • 5:35 - 5:41
    make the argument valid? The question here
    is, can we add a suppressed premise that
  • 5:41 - 5:46
    will turn this invalid argument into a
    valid argument? Here's one that will do
  • 5:46 - 5:52
    the trick. A box that contains a sweater
    doesn't rattle when shaken. Now the
  • 5:52 - 5:58
    argument looks like this. This box rattles
    when I shake it. The box that contains a
  • 5:58 - 6:03
    sweater doesn't rattle when shaken, so
    this box doesn't contain a sweater. The
  • 6:03 - 6:09
    explicit premise is that this box rattles
    when I shake it. The suppressed premise is
  • 6:09 - 6:15
    that a box that contains a sweater doesn't
    rattle when shaken and together they are
  • 6:15 - 6:21
    suppose support the conclusion that this
    box doesn't contain a sweater, but do they
  • 6:21 - 6:27
    really support that conclusion? Is the
    argument valid? Well, it's valid only if
  • 6:27 - 6:31
    there's no possibility that the premises
    are true and the conclusions false.
  • 6:31 - 6:36
    Without the suppressed premise we saw this
    might be possible, because my wife might
  • 6:36 - 6:41
    be fooling me and putting rocks around the
    sweater. So let's see if that's going to
  • 6:41 - 6:46
    ruin the validity of this argument. No!
    Because if the sweater has got rocks
  • 6:46 - 6:51
    around it so it makes noise when I shake
    it, then the premise that says a box that
  • 6:51 - 6:55
    contains a sweater doesn't rattle when
    shaken turns out to be fal se.
  • 6:55 - 7:01
    So that's not a case where the premises
    are true and the conclusions false because
  • 7:01 - 7:06
    the premise is false in that case. So, by
    adding this premise, we actually succeeded
  • 7:06 - 7:12
    in making the argument valid. The problem
    of course is that validity is not enough
  • 7:12 - 7:18
    for a good argument, as we saw several
    lectures ago. You can have an argument
  • 7:18 - 7:24
    that's very bad, when the argument is not
    sound. What we want really is soundness.
  • 7:24 - 7:29
    So, that's why we need the next step,
    mainly, check the supressed premises for
  • 7:29 - 7:35
    truth. Assess whether they're true or
    false. And, if they're not true, then you
  • 7:35 - 7:41
    need to qualify them, in order to make
    them true. Cuz you don't want to claim
  • 7:41 - 7:47
    that the person giving the argument was
    assuming this falsehood, when the didn't
  • 7:47 - 7:53
    have to. So let's see if there's some way
    to qualify this suppressed premise in
  • 7:53 - 8:00
    order to make it true. How can we qualify
    this premise to make it true? How are we
  • 8:00 - 8:07
    going to do that? Let me think. Oh. What
    about that little word only. You could add
  • 8:07 - 8:15
    that. You could say, a box that contains
    only a sweater doesn't rattle when shaken.
  • 8:16 - 8:21
    But the word only, what exactly does that
    mean? We need to clarify that. What
  • 8:21 - 8:26
    exactly is the word only exclude? It
    excludes something, that's the function of
  • 8:26 - 8:33
    the word only, but what does it exclude?
    Well. It probably excludes other things
  • 8:33 - 8:39
    that might make the rattling sound like if
    my wife put rocks in the box. So we can
  • 8:39 - 8:45
    clarify this premise by saying a box that
    contains only a sweater and not anything
  • 8:45 - 8:52
    else that might make a rattling sound when
    shaken, won't rattle when shaken. Well, is
  • 8:52 - 8:58
    that premise true? Well, you might quibble
    about details but it's close enough for
  • 8:58 - 9:03
    now. What we need to do though is to go
    back and determine whether, when we put
  • 9:03 - 9:09
    that suppressed premise in, the argument's
    valid. And the argument now looks like
  • 9:09 - 9:15
    this. This box does rattle when shaken,
    and a box doesn't rattle when shaken if it
  • 9:15 - 9:22
    contains only a sweater and not anything
    else that makes a rattling sound. So this
  • 9:22 - 9:29
    box doesn't contain a sweater. Is that
    valid? Well, no, for the same reason we s
  • 9:29 - 9:35
    aw before, because my wife might be a
    trickster who puts rocks around my sweater
  • 9:35 - 9:42
    in the birthday present box in order to
    fool me. Then, the premises can be true,
  • 9:42 - 9:48
    and the conclusion false. It's possible
    that, the first premise is true. This box
  • 9:48 - 9:55
    rattles when I shake it. And the second
    premise is true, a box doesn't rattle when
  • 9:55 - 10:00
    shaken if it contains only a sweater and
    nothing else that makes a rattling sound.
  • 10:00 - 10:05
    But it's false that this box doesn't
    contain a sweater, cuz it still does
  • 10:05 - 10:09
    contain a sweater, and it contains a
    sweater in addition to those pesky little
  • 10:09 - 10:14
    rocks that make all that rattling noise.
    Well, if your argument's not valid, we've
  • 10:14 - 10:18
    got to go back to that other step and add
    another suppressed premise. Remember how I
  • 10:18 - 10:22
    told you how these different steps within
    this stage work in tandem and what's
  • 10:22 - 10:26
    happening is you've got to check it for
    validity, add a suppressed premise,
  • 10:26 - 10:30
    recheck for validity, maybe add another
    suppressed premise, and that's what we're
  • 10:30 - 10:35
    doing now. So what kind of suppressed
    premised can we add. Well, we could add my
  • 10:35 - 10:41
    wife is not a trickster but basically that
    amounts to she wouldn't put rocks in a
  • 10:41 - 10:47
    birthday present with a sweater in order
    to fool me. So we could make that a little
  • 10:47 - 10:52
    more explicit by making the suppressed
    premise something like this. If this box
  • 10:52 - 10:58
    contains a sweater, then it only contains
    a sweater and it doesn't include anything
  • 10:58 - 11:03
    else that would make a rattling sound when
    shaken. And now we can stick that as an
  • 11:03 - 11:08
    extra suppressed premise into the
    argument. Now the argument looks like
  • 11:08 - 11:15
    this. This box rattles when I shake it. A
    box doesn't rattle when shaken, if it
  • 11:15 - 11:21
    contains only a sweater and not anything
    else that makes a rattling noise when
  • 11:21 - 11:28
    shaken. If this box contains a sweater,
    then it contains only a sweater and
  • 11:28 - 11:34
    doesn't contain anything that rattles when
    shaken. So this box does not contain a
  • 11:34 - 11:40
    sweater. Now we have an argument that's
    valid. And the suppressed premises are
  • 11:40 - 11:45
    true, at least given our life's not a
    trickster, which she's not, I assure you.
  • 11:45 - 11:51
    And it looks like we have a sound rec
    onstruction, just what we were looking
  • 11:51 - 11:56
    for. Admittedly, this argument is a lot
    longer and more convoluted than the
  • 11:56 - 12:02
    original, and that shows why people
    suppress premises instead of talking the
  • 12:02 - 12:07
    way this argument goes. And of course,
    many people would be perfectly well
  • 12:07 - 12:13
    convinced by the original argument because
    they share the assumptions that are in the
  • 12:13 - 12:18
    suppressed premises. So why do we go
    through all the trouble to go through this
  • 12:18 - 12:23
    process and add the suppressed premises?
    Remember, the reason is that we want to
  • 12:23 - 12:28
    understand the pathway between the
    premises and conclusion. We want to
  • 12:28 - 12:33
    understand how the reasoning works step by
    step by step. And we want to do that
  • 12:33 - 12:38
    because sometimes people are going to
    include suppressed premises that aren't
  • 12:38 - 12:42
    true, and we want to bring them out and
    make those assumptions explicit so that we
  • 12:42 - 12:47
    can assess them for truth and falsehood.
    And when you're talking to somebody you
  • 12:47 - 12:52
    trust, you might not have to do that and
    it's okay to suppress premises. But when
  • 12:52 - 12:56
    you really want to know whether the
    argument's any good, that's when you want
  • 12:56 - 13:01
    to fill it out with the suppressed
    premises. The point of going into detail
  • 13:01 - 13:05
    on this example is to illustrate this
    stage of reconstruction. You want to
  • 13:05 - 13:10
    assess the argument for validity, add
    suppressed premises that make it valid.
  • 13:10 - 13:15
    Check them for truth. If they're not true,
    you qualify them, and then you go back and
  • 13:15 - 13:20
    see whether that qualification made the
    argument not valid anymore. And you go
  • 13:20 - 13:25
    back and forth and back and forth until
    you've got a sound reconstruction. The
  • 13:25 - 13:30
    same steps are going to apply to all kinds
    of suppressed premises. And sure enough,
  • 13:30 - 13:34
    there are all kinds of suppressed
    premises. So let's go through a few
  • 13:34 - 13:40
    examples a lot more quickly in order to
    show the variety of suppressed premises
  • 13:40 - 13:47
    that are assumed in arguments. Here's one
    example. Abraham Lincoln turned 40. On
  • 13:47 - 13:58
    February twelfth, 1849. Therefore, Charles
    Darwin also turned 40 on February twelfth,
  • 13:58 - 14:04
    1849. Now, is that argument valid? No
    chance. Of course it's possible for the
  • 14:04 - 14:10
    premise to be true and the conclus ion
    false. So we have to add a suppressed
  • 14:10 - 14:15
    premise. The suppressed premise is, that
    Abraham Lincoln and Charles Darwin were
  • 14:15 - 14:21
    born on the same day. And they were, it
    happened to be February twelfth, 1809. So
  • 14:21 - 14:27
    now, we've filled out the argument.
    Abraham Lincoln turned 40 on February
  • 14:27 - 14:33
    twelfth, 1849. Abraham Lincoln and Charles
    Darwin were born on the same day,
  • 14:33 - 14:40
    therefore Charles Darwin also turned 40 on
    February twelfth, 1849. Now is the
  • 14:40 - 14:47
    argument valid? No. It's still not valid.
    Cuz Darwin might have died before 1849. So
  • 14:47 - 14:53
    we have to add another suppressed premise.
    Mainly, that both Abraham Lincoln and
  • 14:53 - 15:00
    Charles Darwin lived beyond 40. So now we
    have a fuller argument. Abraham Lincoln
  • 15:00 - 15:07
    turned 40 on February twelfth, 1849.
    Abraham Lincoln and Charles Darwin were
  • 15:07 - 15:14
    born on the same day. Both of them lived
    beyond the age of 40. Therefore, Charles
  • 15:14 - 15:21
    Darwin also turned 40 on February twelve,
    1849. Now the argument looks pretty good.
  • 15:21 - 15:27
    We had to have two suppressed premises but
    we finally have a valid argument. And what
  • 15:27 - 15:31
    this shows is that sometimes the
    suppressed premises are purely factual
  • 15:31 - 15:37
    matters. In this case that they were born
    on the same day and that they both lived
  • 15:37 - 15:42
    beyond 40. So sometimes we have factual
    suppressed premises. Here's another quick
  • 15:42 - 15:47
    example. You ought to obey her because
    she's your mother. Here, the premise is
  • 15:47 - 15:52
    that she's your mother and the conclusion
    is that you ought to obey her. Well, is
  • 15:52 - 15:58
    that argument valid? No way cause it's
    possible that she's your mother but it's
  • 15:58 - 16:03
    false that you ought to obey her. When
    could that happen? Maybe, she was like
  • 16:03 - 16:09
    abusive or stupid or whatever. Then maybe
    you ought not to obey her even though she
  • 16:09 - 16:14
    is your mother. So we have to add a
    premise, namely, you ought to obey your
  • 16:14 - 16:19
    mother. Now we can say she's your mother,
    you ought to obey your mother therefore
  • 16:19 - 16:25
    you ought to obey her, but of course that
    a supressed premise you ought to obey your
  • 16:25 - 16:29
    mother is questionable because maybe she
    was abusive or stupid. So let's add
  • 16:29 - 16:34
    another supressed premise that your mother
    was not abusive or stupid, of course we a
  • 16:34 - 16:39
    lso have to qualify that moral premise
    that you ought to obey your mother if
  • 16:39 - 16:44
    she's not abusive or stupid. And now the
    argument looks like this - she's your
  • 16:44 - 16:49
    mother, you ought to obey your mother if
    she's not abusive or stupid. Your mother
  • 16:49 - 16:55
    was not abusive or stupid. Therefore, you
    ought to obey her. An notice that here, we
  • 16:55 - 17:00
    added a moral premise about the fact that
    you ought to obey your mother under
  • 17:00 - 17:06
    certain conditions. Namely, she's not
    abusive or stupid. And the second premise
  • 17:06 - 17:11
    is she was not abusive or stupid. So, we
    have a moral premise and a factual
  • 17:11 - 17:16
    premise, both being suppressed in the
    argument that you ought to obey her
  • 17:16 - 17:23
    because she's your mother. Here's another
    . It's the Sabbath, so you ought to go to
  • 17:23 - 17:29
    synagogue. Well, that's clearly not valid.
    One suppressed premise is that you're
  • 17:29 - 17:34
    Jewish. The other suppressed premise is
    you haven't been to synagogue already
  • 17:34 - 17:40
    today, on this Sabbath. And the third
    suppressed premise is a religious norm,
  • 17:40 - 17:46
    mainly Jews ought to go to the synagogue
    on the Sabbath. And you need that whole
  • 17:46 - 17:51
    bunch of suppressed premises in order to
    get from the premise, that it's the
  • 17:51 - 17:56
    Sabbath, to the conclusion, that you ought
    to go to synagogue. And of course all of
  • 17:56 - 18:02
    those premises might be questionable. Some
    people would question them. Some people
  • 18:02 - 18:07
    would deny them, but the point here is to
    figure out what's being assumed by someone
  • 18:07 - 18:12
    who gave the original argument. And
    anybody who says it's the Sabbath, so you
  • 18:12 - 18:16
    ought to go to synagogue, seems to be
    assuming you're Jewish, you haven't been
  • 18:16 - 18:21
    already, and Jews ought to go to the
    synagogue on the Sabbath. So what these
  • 18:21 - 18:27
    suppressed premises do is they bring out
    the assumptions that somebody who gave
  • 18:27 - 18:33
    that argument must have had in mind. The
    last case is a little bit trickier. It has
  • 18:33 - 18:39
    to do with linguistic suppressed premises.
    Jen and Bob are first cousins, therefore
  • 18:39 - 18:47
    they share a grandparent. Now, in order to
    understand that argument, you have to know
  • 18:47 - 18:52
    that first cousins always share a
    grandparent. That just follows from the
  • 18:52 - 18:59
    definition of what a first cousin is. But
    i t's not quite so obvious, is that
  • 18:59 - 19:04
    biological sisters are female. And so,
    there's even more need to bring out that
  • 19:04 - 19:09
    linguistics suppressed premise in this
    case. But it's still not necessary to make
  • 19:09 - 19:15
    the argument valid. It's just not possible
    that Janet and Bob are first cousins, and
  • 19:15 - 19:20
    they don't share a grandparent. Because
    the suppressed premise is purely
  • 19:20 - 19:25
    linguistic, so it's necessarily true, so
    you can't possibly be first cousins
  • 19:25 - 19:30
    without sharing a grandparent. Still, the
    point of bringing out linguistic
  • 19:30 - 19:35
    suppressed premises is to show every
    little step along the way. The argument
  • 19:35 - 19:40
    might be valid without those suppressed
    linguistic premises, but we won't
  • 19:40 - 19:45
    understand why it's valid and why the
    reasoning goes through unless we add the
  • 19:45 - 19:51
    linguistics suppressed premise. So it's
    worth doing that. Shh. Here's a trick.
  • 19:51 - 20:00
    Don't tell anybody. Okay? It's just
    between me and you. You can always make
  • 20:00 - 20:07
    any argument valid just by adding a
    suppressed premise that says if the
  • 20:07 - 20:14
    premises are true, then the conclusion is
    true. But don't tell anybody, because if
  • 20:14 - 20:20
    people start doing that, and they start
    making the argument valid that way, with
  • 20:20 - 20:26
    that suppressed premise, we're never going
    to understand the pathway of reasoning. It
  • 20:26 - 20:31
    makes the argument valid, but it doesn't
    serve the real purpose of adding
  • 20:32 - 20:37
    suppressed premises which is to understand
    the pathway of reasoning. So you can do
  • 20:37 - 20:43
    that. It's a trick. It makes that argument
    valid but it doesn't achieve our goal
  • 20:43 - 20:48
    because our goal is not just to make the
    argument valid, it's to make the argument
  • 20:48 - 20:55
    valid so that we can understand the
    pathway of reasoning. So it's important to
  • 20:55 - 21:02
    know that trick, but don't use it unless
    you have to. The examples so far have been
  • 21:02 - 21:08
    pretty trivial, I admit it. But the same
    points apply in very important context
  • 21:08 - 21:14
    such as politic debates, politician can
    suppress premises in perfectly legitimate
  • 21:14 - 21:20
    ways. They're just trying to save time and
    make their arguments more efficient, maybe
  • 21:20 - 21:26
    even sometimes clearer because you don't
    have to add all those little details. But
  • 21:26 - 21:32
    sometimes politicia ns abuse suppressed
    premises. They take things for granted
  • 21:32 - 21:38
    that they shouldn't be taking for granted.
    Here's an example. A politician might
  • 21:38 - 21:44
    argue, my opponent is soft on crime
    because he's opposed to the death penalty.
  • 21:44 - 21:50
    Well, that assumes, as a suppressed
    premise, that anyone who's opposed to the
  • 21:50 - 21:56
    death penalty must be soft on crime. And
    if the politician were to come out and say
  • 21:56 - 22:01
    that, it would seem pretty questionable,
    and that's probably why he suppresses it.
  • 22:02 - 22:07
    And then another politician might say, my
    opponent is in favor of the death penalty,
  • 22:07 - 22:13
    so he must not have read all the recent
    studies that show that the death penalty
  • 22:13 - 22:19
    doesn't deter. Well that argument assumes
    the suppressed premise that if you've read
  • 22:19 - 22:24
    those studies you'ld be convinced by them,
    and that the only point of the death
  • 22:24 - 22:30
    penalty is deterrence. But the point is
    that politicians talking about extremely
  • 22:30 - 22:34
    important issues can take things for
    granted, that if they were brought into
  • 22:34 - 22:39
    the light of day will be questionable, and
    that's why they hide them. So when you're
  • 22:39 - 22:44
    listening to people give arguments on
    important issues in your life, then you
  • 22:44 - 22:50
    ought to be looking for these suppressed
    premises and asking yourself whether or
  • 22:50 - 22:56
    not you really ought to be agreeing with
    them about that assumption. Finally, we
  • 22:56 - 23:02
    finished reconstruction. Yipee, right? Oh,
    no, not quite, because there's one more
  • 23:02 - 23:07
    stage, and that stage is drawing a
    conclusion. Of course, if we've come up
  • 23:07 - 23:12
    with a sound reconstruction, then we know
    that the argument is sound, and we know
  • 23:12 - 23:19
    that the conclusion is true, because every
    sound argument has a true conclusion. But
  • 23:19 - 23:24
    if we don't come up with a sound
    reconstruction, then what do we say? Well,
  • 23:24 - 23:28
    you've got to ask, whose fault is it? It
    might be the fault of the argument. Maybe
  • 23:28 - 23:33
    we couldn't come up with a sound
    reconstruction because there just is no
  • 23:33 - 23:37
    sound reconstruction. But maybe we
    couldn't come up with a sound
  • 23:37 - 23:42
    reconstruction because we just weren't
    imaginative enough, or try hard enough.
  • 23:42 - 23:48
    Still, if we try really long an hard, and
    charitably interpret the a rgument as best
  • 23:48 - 23:53
    we can to make it, look as good as we can,
    and we still can't make it sound. Then,
  • 23:53 - 23:58
    we've at least got reason to believe that
    the argument's not sound. Of course, that
  • 23:58 - 24:04
    doesn't mean that the conclusion's not
    true, because unsound arguments can still
  • 24:04 - 24:09
    have true conclusions. But at least we
    know that this argument doesn't prove that
  • 24:09 - 24:14
    the conclusion is true. And so, this
    method of reconstruction can lead us
  • 24:14 - 24:19
    either to the belief that the argument is
    sound, because we found the sound
  • 24:19 - 24:25
    reconstruction, or to the conclusion is
    not sound, because we tried long and hard
  • 24:25 - 24:30
    to find a sound reconstruction that
    didn't, but that's still not going to show
  • 24:30 - 24:37
    us that the conclusion of the argument is
    false. The point of reconstruction then is
  • 24:37 - 24:42
    to reach a conclusion on this issue of is
    the argument sound or not. And if we try
  • 24:42 - 24:48
    our best and do it as well as we can and
    charitably, then we can be justified in
  • 24:48 - 24:51
    believing that the argument is sound or
    not.
Title:
Lecture 3-6 - Fill in Gaps and Conclude
jngiam edited English subtitles for Lecture 3-6 - Fill in Gaps and Conclude
jngiam added a translation

English subtitles

Revisions