Return to Video

Lecture 2 - What is an Argument?

  • 0:02 - 0:06
    Well, I hope the first lecture convinced
    you that arguments really matter.
  • 0:06 - 0:09
    Of course, they're not the only thing that
    matters,
  • 0:09 - 0:13
    There's more to life than reason and
    arguments. But, they are something that
  • 0:13 - 0:16
    matters, and they matter a lot.
    So, we need to understand arguments.
  • 0:16 - 0:21
    And the first step in understanding
    arguments is to figure out what arguments
  • 0:21 - 0:24
    are.
    And the first step in understanding what
  • 0:24 - 0:29
    arguments are is to figure out what
    arguments are not because we want to
  • 0:29 - 0:34
    distinguish arguments from all those
    things that don't count as arguing.
  • 0:34 - 0:39
    And the best source of information about
    what arguments are not is, of course,
  • 0:39 - 0:43
    Monty Python.
    Well, that was pretty silly wasn't it?
  • 0:43 - 0:48
    But it in the midst of all that silliness,
    we find some truth because, after all,
  • 0:48 - 0:52
    many members of the Monty Python troupe
    were philosophy majors.
  • 0:52 - 0:57
    So, each room represents a kind of thing
    that we need to distinguish from
  • 0:57 - 1:01
    arguments.
    So, let's think first about getting hit on
  • 1:01 - 1:03
    the head lessons.
    Oh.
  • 1:03 - 1:07
    Arguments are not like hitting
    people on the head.
  • 1:07 - 1:12
    You hit people on the head when you
    wrestle.
  • 1:12 - 1:15
    The point is that arguments are not
    fights.
  • 1:15 - 1:18
    You don't win an argument by hitting
    somebody on the head.
  • 1:18 - 1:23
    Sometimes, little children say that their
    parents are arguing when they're really
  • 1:23 - 1:27
    having a verbal fight.
    All this fighting, I might as well
  • 1:27 - 1:31
    be back with my parents.
    Damn it, George, I told you if you didn't
  • 1:31 - 1:35
    quit drinking I'd leave you.
    Well, guess that makes you a liar because I'm
  • 1:35 - 1:40
    drunk as hell and you're still here.
    But, you cannot win an argument
  • 1:40 - 1:46
    just by yelling at someone.
    That doesn't make the argument any better,
  • 1:46 - 1:52
    because that's not the point of arguing.
    Another room in the Monty Python skit
  • 1:52 - 1:56
    involves abuse.
    Don't give me that, you snotty-faced heap
  • 1:56 - 2:00
    of parrot droppings.
    Now, abuse is one of the things
  • 2:00 - 2:04
    you do with language, but it's not the
    same as arguing.
  • 2:04 - 2:08
    You cannot win an argument simply by
    calling your opponent a stupid git.
  • 2:08 - 2:12
    Stupid git.
    And the point of this course is not to
  • 2:12 - 2:17
    teach you to go back and abuse your
    roommate by calling them nasty names,
  • 2:17 - 2:22
    That will not help you win any argument.
    It also won't help you win any friends.
  • 2:22 - 2:25
    And another room in the skit has to do
    with complaining.
  • 2:25 - 2:29
    Nothing happens, you might just as well
    not bother, and my back hurts, and we'll
  • 2:29 - 2:32
    never have a fine day.
    But all those complaints don't amount to
  • 2:32 - 2:34
    an argument either.
    They're just expressing your emotion about
  • 2:34 - 2:38
    the situation.
    Arguing is something different from all of
  • 2:38 - 2:40
    those rooms.
    So, what is arguing?
  • 2:40 - 2:43
    Well, at one point, one of the characters
    says,
  • 2:43 - 2:46
    Well, arguing is not the same as
    contradiction.
  • 2:46 - 2:48
    It can be.
    No, it can't.
  • 2:48 - 2:52
    So, what do they mean by a contradiction?
    In British English, to say a
  • 2:52 - 2:56
    contradiction, is just to deny the person,
    or contradict what they said.
  • 2:56 - 3:01
    But contradicting what the person said,
    that is denying it, is not arguing.
  • 3:01 - 3:04
    I can say,
    What do you think is the best flavor of
  • 3:04 - 3:07
    ice-cream in the world?
    Well, I have my favorite. I know what the
  • 3:07 - 3:11
    best flavor is.
    The best flavor is Ben and Jerry's Coconut
  • 3:11 - 3:13
    Almond Fudge Chip ice cream; there's
    nothing better.
  • 3:13 - 3:19
    And then, you say, no it isn't.
    Well, you haven't argued that it isn't and
  • 3:19 - 3:24
    I haven't argued that it is.
    We're just disagreeing with each other.
  • 3:24 - 3:28
    We haven't given any reason for any of the
    positions that we've adopted yet.
  • 3:28 - 3:32
    So, as Monty Python says later on, in a
    different character,
  • 3:32 - 3:38
    Argument is an intellectual process.
    It's a process not just of asserting your
  • 3:38 - 3:43
    views, but of giving some kind of reason
    for your views.
  • 3:43 - 3:48
    So, the next definition that Monty Python
    gives of an argument is, that an argument
  • 3:48 - 3:52
    is a connected series of statements to
    establish a proposition.
  • 3:52 - 3:56
    I take it they mean, intended to establish
    a certain proposition.
  • 3:56 - 3:59
    So, that's a pretty cool definition, if
    you think about it
  • 3:59 - 4:02
    because it tells you what an argument is
    made of.
  • 4:02 - 4:06
    It's a series of statements, and
    statements are made in language, so
  • 4:06 - 4:10
    arguments are made of language.
    It also tells you what the purpose of
  • 4:10 - 4:13
    argument is.
    The purpose of argument, they say, is to
  • 4:13 - 4:18
    establish a certain proposition.
    So now we have a pretty neat definition of
  • 4:18 - 4:21
    argument.
    This definition gives us a nice contrast
  • 4:21 - 4:26
    because there are lots of other series of
    statements or sentences that don't count
  • 4:26 - 4:31
    as arguments because they're not intended
    to establish a proposition.
  • 4:31 - 4:36
    Consider for example, a novel which has
    statements about what's going on, but it's
  • 4:36 - 4:40
    not necessarily trying to establish any
    particular proposition.
  • 4:40 - 4:44
    Or a dictionary might have a series of
    definitions, but it's not intended to
  • 4:44 - 4:49
    establish a certain proposition.
    Instead, novels and dictionaries order
  • 4:49 - 4:54
    sentences in a different way.
    They order them either chronologically or
  • 4:54 - 4:57
    alphabetically,
    whereas arguments are trying to put
  • 4:57 - 5:03
    statements into a certain structure that
    reflects the order of reasoning in order
  • 5:03 - 5:06
    to establish the proposition, according to
    Monty Python.
  • 5:06 - 5:12
    But Monty Python, no matter how great they
    are, and they are great,
  • 5:12 - 5:18
    didn't get it quite right because the
    purpose of an argument is not always to
  • 5:18 - 5:24
    establish a proposition because some
    propositions are conclusions of
  • 5:24 - 5:28
    arguments we already knew.
    Consider, for example, a mathematical
  • 5:28 - 5:32
    proof.
    If someone tries to prove the Pythagorean
  • 5:32 - 5:36
    Theorem in geometry, people already
    believe the theorem.
  • 5:36 - 5:42
    They already new that it was true,
    so they weren't trying to establish the
  • 5:42 - 5:44
    proposition.
    But the proof does something else.
  • 5:44 - 5:49
    It shows you how that proposition is
    connected to the axioms of the system and
  • 5:49 - 5:52
    helps you understand why the proposition
    is true.
  • 5:52 - 5:57
    And we'll see that other arguments, like
    explanations, do the same thing.
  • 5:57 - 6:02
    So sometimes, arguments are intended to
    establish a proposition, like Monty Python
  • 6:02 - 6:04
    said.
    But in other cases, they're intended to
  • 6:04 - 6:09
    help us understand the proposition and the
    reasons why the proposition is true.
  • 6:09 - 6:14
    So, we want to distinguish reasons to
    believe that the proposition is true from
  • 6:14 - 6:19
    reasons why the proposition is true.
    And arguments can do both of those things.
  • 6:19 - 6:25
    So, we need a somewhat broader definition
    of argument to cover these different kinds
  • 6:25 - 6:29
    of reasons.
    We'll think of an argument as a connected
  • 6:29 - 6:36
    series of sentences, or statements, or
    propositions where some of these sentences
  • 6:36 - 6:42
    or statements or propositions are premises
    and one of them is the conclusion.
  • 6:42 - 6:48
    And the ones that are premises are
    intended to provide some kind of reason
  • 6:48 - 6:53
    for the one that's the conclusion.
    This definition is useful in many ways.
  • 6:53 - 6:58
    First of all, it tells us what the parts
    of the arguments are,
  • 6:58 - 7:03
    The premises and the conclusion.
    Secondly, it tells you what the argument's
  • 7:03 - 7:06
    made of.
    It's made of language because sentences
  • 7:06 - 7:10
    and statements and propositions are made
    in language.
  • 7:10 - 7:13
    Third, it tells you the purpose of
    argument.
  • 7:13 - 7:18
    To give a reason for the conclusion.
    Fourth, a nice feature is that it's very
  • 7:18 - 7:21
    flexible, because there are lots of
    different kinds of reasons.
  • 7:21 - 7:26
    We don't want our definition to be too
    narrow because then it won't cover all the
  • 7:26 - 7:30
    different kinds of arguments.
    And the notion of reason captures the
  • 7:30 - 7:35
    different kinds of relations between the
    premises and the conclusion in different
  • 7:35 - 7:39
    kinds of arguments.
    So, let's do a few quick exercises to make
  • 7:39 - 7:42
    sure that you understand how this
    definition works.
Title:
Lecture 2 - What is an Argument?
Description:

Last modified: 11/14/2012 15:52 pm

more » « less
Video Language:
English

English subtitles

Revisions