Return to Video

Lecture 3-5 - Organize Parts

  • 0:03 - 0:08
    Welcome back. We've covered stages one
    through three of argument reconstruction
  • 0:08 - 0:13
    namely, close analysis, get down to
    basics, and sharpen edges. In this
  • 0:13 - 0:20
    lecture, we'll cover stage four, which is
    organized parts. Cuz it's not enough to
  • 0:20 - 0:26
    isolate the parts and figure out what they
    are. We need to show how the fit together
  • 0:26 - 0:32
    in a structure so that they work together
    to support the conclusion of the argument.
  • 0:32 - 0:38
    To see how this works, let's start with an
    example. Consider this example. That
  • 0:38 - 0:44
    fertilizer won't help the roses bloom cuz
    there is already a lot of nitrogen in the
  • 0:44 - 0:50
    soil. So, the fertilizer will make the
    nitrogen levels too high. Of course, so is
  • 0:50 - 0:55
    a conclusion marker so one conclusion is
    that, the fertilizer will make the
  • 0:55 - 1:01
    nitrogen levels too high. And then, you
    might think that one might have put the
  • 1:01 - 1:06
    argument into standard form goes like
    this. Premise one is that fertilizer won't
  • 1:06 - 1:12
    make the roses bloom. Premise two is the
    nitrogen levels in the soil are already
  • 1:12 - 1:17
    high. And then, the conclusion is that the
    fertilizer will make the nitrogen levels
  • 1:17 - 1:22
    too high. But that doesn't really make any
    sense, if you think about it. How could
  • 1:22 - 1:27
    the fact that the roses won't bloom be a
    reason to believe that the nitrogen levels
  • 1:27 - 1:32
    are too high? This couldn't be a reason
    for that. So, we might just have the wrong
  • 1:32 - 1:38
    structure. However, there is another
    argument marker. This time it's a premise
  • 1:38 - 1:43
    marker, because. And that indicates that
    the claim that there's already a lot of
  • 1:43 - 1:49
    nitrogen in the soil is a premise. But
    what is the conclusion for that premise?
  • 1:49 - 1:55
    That's supposed to show that the
    fertilizer won't make the roses bloom. So,
  • 1:55 - 2:01
    we've missed that part of the structure if
    we put it in standard form, the way we
  • 2:01 - 2:06
    first thought. The trick here is that
    there are really two conclusions. One
  • 2:06 - 2:11
    conclusion is that the fertilizer won't
    help the roses bloom, and another
  • 2:11 - 2:17
    conclusion is that the fertilizer will
    make the nitrogen levels too high. But
  • 2:17 - 2:23
    each argument's just supposed to have one
    conclusion. So, how are we going to put
  • 2:23 - 2:29
    this into a structure? The solution is
    that there are two arguments. One is that
  • 2:29 - 2:34
    the nitrogen levels in the soil are
    already high. Therefore, adding the
  • 2:34 - 2:39
    fertilizer will make them too high. And
    the second argument is that, adding the
  • 2:39 - 2:45
    fertilizer will make the nitrogen levels
    too high, therefore the fertilizer will
  • 2:45 - 2:52
    not make the roses bloom. Now notice that
    one argument really builds on the other
  • 2:52 - 2:59
    because the conclusion of the first
    argument is really a premise in the second
  • 2:59 - 3:05
    argument. So, we can represent them as two
    separate arguments. But we can also put
  • 3:05 - 3:11
    them together in a chain. So that the
    argument says, the nitrogen levels in the
  • 3:11 - 3:16
    soil are already high. Therefore, adding
    fertilizer will make them too high. And
  • 3:16 - 3:23
    therefore, adding fertilizer will not help
    the roses bloom. Now, if we take that
  • 3:23 - 3:29
    whole structure and we try to represent it
    in a diagram, and we represent each
  • 3:29 - 3:36
    premise with a number, which is the number
    that was given in the standard form, then
  • 3:36 - 3:42
    we can simply have premise one with an
    arrow to premise two indicating that
  • 3:42 - 3:48
    premise one is a reason for premise two.
    And then, another arrow going from premise
  • 3:48 - 3:54
    two to premise three to indicate that two
    is a reason for three. In a way, we've got
  • 3:54 - 3:59
    two premises and two conclusions because
    that one kind in the middle, number two,
  • 3:59 - 4:05
    operates as a conclusion in the first
    argument and a premise in the second
  • 4:05 - 4:10
    argument. But overall, I hope the diagram,
    its clear. Well, I want to call this
  • 4:10 - 4:14
    linear structure. When you have one
    premise giving reason for a conclusion
  • 4:14 - 4:19
    which is then premise for another
    conclusion, then they form a line in the
  • 4:19 - 4:24
    diagram them in the way that I am
    proposing. Arguments can have other
  • 4:24 - 4:29
    structures, too. In particular, sometimes
    there's more than one premise associated
  • 4:29 - 4:35
    with a single conclusion. And this can
    happen in two ways. The first, we're going
  • 4:34 - 4:40
    to call the branching structure, and the
    second we're going to call the joint
  • 4:40 - 4:45
    structure. Here is an example of the
    branching structure. I'm not going to go
  • 4:45 - 4:51
    to the movie with you because I don't like
    horror flicks. And besides, I'm too busy.
  • 4:51 - 4:56
    The word beca use is a premise marker. So
    that indicates that the conclusion is
  • 4:56 - 5:01
    that, I'm not going to go to the movie
    with you. And there are two premises. One
  • 5:01 - 5:06
    is, I don't like horror flicks, and the
    other is, I'm too busy. Now, you might
  • 5:06 - 5:12
    think that, that could just be put in the
    old linear structure that we already saw.
  • 5:12 - 5:18
    But then, the argument's going to look
    like this. I don't like horror flicks.
  • 5:18 - 5:23
    Therefore, I'm too busy. Therefore, I'm
    not going to go to the movie. But, wait a
  • 5:23 - 5:28
    minute. The fact that I don't like horror
    flicks doesn't mean I'm too busy. That
  • 5:28 - 5:33
    doesn't make any sense. Oh, maybe it's the
    other way around. I'm too busy. Therefore,
  • 5:33 - 5:38
    I don't like horror flicks. Therefore, I'm
    not going to go to that movie with you.
  • 5:38 - 5:43
    That doesn't make any sense either. The
    fact that I'm too busy isn't why I don't
  • 5:43 - 5:48
    like horror flicks. The problem is, there
    are two premises here but neither one is a
  • 5:48 - 5:52
    reason for the other, as we saw in the
    linear structure. Instead, in this
  • 5:52 - 5:57
    branching structure, each premise is
    operating independently. There's one
  • 5:57 - 6:02
    argument. I don't like horror flicks,
    therefore I'm not going to go to that
  • 6:02 - 6:07
    movie with you. There's another argument.
    I'm too busy, therefore I'm not going to
  • 6:07 - 6:12
    that movie with you. And each premise by
    itself is a sufficient reason not to go to
  • 6:12 - 6:16
    the movie with you. I mean, just think
    about it. If I wasn't too busy, but I
  • 6:16 - 6:20
    didn't like horror flicks, I wouldn't go
    to the movie. But if I liked horror
  • 6:20 - 6:25
    flicks, but I was too busy, I still would
    go to the movie. So, each premise by
  • 6:25 - 6:30
    itself is enough, and they operate
    independently. That's what makes this a
  • 6:30 - 6:35
    branching structure instead of a linear
    structure. Let's diagram it and you'll see
  • 6:35 - 6:41
    why we call it a branching structure. One
    way to diagram it would be to simply draw
  • 6:41 - 6:46
    an arrow between premise one and the
    conclusion two. And then, there's a
  • 6:46 - 6:51
    separate argument, so you draw another
    arrow from one star, another premise, to
  • 6:51 - 6:57
    conclusion two. And that's okay. But,
    notice that it doesn't show you that both
  • 6:57 - 7:02
    premises are reasons for the same
    conclusion. So, to capture t hat aspect of
  • 7:02 - 7:08
    the structure, that both Premise one and
    Premise one Star support the same
  • 7:08 - 7:14
    conclusion, namely two. It's better to
    diagram it so that there's an arrow that
  • 7:14 - 7:21
    runs independently from both premises to a
    single instance of conclusion two, as you
  • 7:21 - 7:25
    see on the diagram on the screen. And that
    should show you why we're calling it a
  • 7:25 - 7:29
    branching structure cuz it kind of
    branches, it looks like the branches of a
  • 7:29 - 7:33
    tree. Okay. Well, it doesn't really look
    like the branches of a tree, but you get
  • 7:33 - 7:36
    the idea. We're going to call it a
    branching structure. Next, we have to
  • 7:36 - 7:41
    separate this branching structure from
    what we're going to call the joint
  • 7:41 - 7:46
    structure. The difference is that in the
    branching structure, the premises provide
  • 7:46 - 7:51
    independent support for the conclusion.
    Whereas, in this joint structure, they
  • 7:51 - 7:56
    work together and they're not going to
    have force independent of each-other. It's
  • 7:56 - 8:01
    like the joint in your leg, which joins
    together the calf with the thigh. And, if
  • 8:01 - 8:05
    you didn't have both, it wouldn't work
    very well. So, we're going to call it a
  • 8:05 - 8:12
    joint structure. Here's an example. For my
    birthday, my wife always gives me either a
  • 8:12 - 8:18
    sweater or a board game. This box does not
    contain a sweater. So, this time she must
  • 8:18 - 8:23
    have given me a board game. Now, notice
    that the argent marker, so, indicates that
  • 8:23 - 8:28
    the conclusion is, this time she must've
    given me a board game. And it's got two
  • 8:28 - 8:33
    premises. And you might think that they
    got a linear structure, and the argument
  • 8:33 - 8:38
    goes something like this. My wife always
    gives me either a sweater or board games.
  • 8:38 - 8:43
    Therefore, this box does not contain a
    sweater. Therefore, this time she gave me
  • 8:43 - 8:48
    board game. That doesn't make any sense,
    right? I mean, the fact that she always
  • 8:48 - 8:53
    gives me either a sweater or board game is
    no reason to believe this box doesn't
  • 8:53 - 8:59
    contain a sweater. Well, okay. Let's try
    it again. Maybe it's a branching
  • 8:59 - 9:05
    structure. That would mean that the
    argument looks like this. My wife always
  • 9:05 - 9:11
    gives me either a sweater or a board game.
    Therefore, this time she gave me a board
  • 9:11 - 9:17
    game. And, as a separat e argument, this
    box does not contain a sweater, therefore
  • 9:17 - 9:21
    this time she must have given me a board
    game. Neither of those arguments makes any
  • 9:21 - 9:26
    sense so it can't be a branching
    structure. Instead, what we have here is
  • 9:26 - 9:32
    the two premises working together. She
    always gives me either a sweater or a
  • 9:32 - 9:38
    board game. And, the second premise, this
    box does not contain a sweater. Those two
  • 9:38 - 9:44
    premises have to work together. It's only
    jointly working together that they can
  • 9:44 - 9:51
    support the conclusion that, this time she
    must have given me a board game. How can
  • 9:51 - 9:57
    we diagram this joint structure? We can
    put a plus sign between premise one and
  • 9:57 - 10:03
    premise two, then draw a line under them
    to show that they work together jointly.
  • 10:03 - 10:09
    And take a line from that line and draw an
    arrow down to the conclusion, just like in
  • 10:09 - 10:14
    the diagram. And this is what we're going
    to call the joint structure. So, we've
  • 10:14 - 10:19
    seen the linear structure, the branching
    structure, and the joint structure. And,
  • 10:19 - 10:25
    we can combine more than one of these
    structures into a single argument. To see
  • 10:25 - 10:30
    how to do this, let's just do a slight
    variation on the previous example. My wife
  • 10:30 - 10:36
    always gives me either a sweater or a
    board game. This is box is not contain a
  • 10:36 - 10:42
    sweater because it rattles when I shake
    it. So, this time she must have given me a
  • 10:42 - 10:49
    board game. This argument combines a
    linear structure with a joint structure.
  • 10:49 - 10:54
    There are two argument markers. One is a
    conclusion marker, so, and that indicates
  • 10:54 - 11:00
    that the eventual conclusion is that she
    must given me a board game this time. But
  • 11:00 - 11:05
    there's also that new word, because, which
    indicates that the fact that it rattles
  • 11:05 - 11:10
    when I shake means that it's not a
    sweater. So, the first stage of the
  • 11:10 - 11:15
    argument in standard form looks like this.
    Premise one, this box rattles when I shake
  • 11:15 - 11:21
    it. Therefore, conclusion, this box does
    not contain a sweater. Stage two says,
  • 11:21 - 11:28
    this box does not contain a sweater, my
    wife always gives me either a sweater or a
  • 11:28 - 11:35
    board game. So, the conclusion, this time,
    she must have given me a board game. And,
  • 11:35 - 11:40
    of course, the conclusion of that fir st
    little argument is identical with the
  • 11:40 - 11:46
    premise of the second argument, so we can
    put them together into a chain. We can
  • 11:46 - 11:51
    say," this box rattles when I shake it, so
    it must not contain a sweater." My wife
  • 11:51 - 11:57
    always gives me a sweater or a board game,
    so this time she must have given me a
  • 11:57 - 12:03
    board game. That's how we get a linear
    structure combined with a joint structure.
  • 12:03 - 12:09
    And we can use our diagram methods to
    diagram this argument the same way we did
  • 12:09 - 12:15
    before. We simply start with premise one,
    the box rattles when I shake it. Draw an
  • 12:15 - 12:21
    arrow down to its conclusion. Namely, the
    box does not contain a sweater. That's
  • 12:21 - 12:27
    two. An then, we show that those are joint
    by adding a plus, premise three. Namely,
  • 12:27 - 12:33
    my wife always gives me either a sweater
    or a board game. Draw a line under them
  • 12:33 - 12:40
    and an arrow from those two together down
    to the eventual conclusion, namely, four
  • 12:40 - 12:45
    that this time she must have given me a
    board game. The fact that the top arrow
  • 12:45 - 12:51
    goes from premise one to two, but does not
    go from premise one to three indicates
  • 12:51 - 12:56
    that, that premises is a reason for two
    but is not a reason for three. So when you
  • 12:56 - 13:02
    use this method to diagram arguments, you
    have to be careful where you draw the
  • 13:02 - 13:07
    arrows. And draw them only where there
    really is a rational connection. That is,
  • 13:07 - 13:13
    where one claim is being presenting as a
    reason for that particular claim that the
  • 13:13 - 13:18
    arrow is pointing towards. Now, almost all
    arguments can be diagrammed using these
  • 13:18 - 13:24
    three simple structures. That is, the
    linear structure, the branching structure,
  • 13:24 - 13:29
    the joint structure, and some combination
    of those three. You can add more premises
  • 13:29 - 13:34
    because you can always add one plus two
    plus three plus four if they're four
  • 13:34 - 13:40
    premises operating together in a joint
    structure. And, you can add extra arrows
  • 13:40 - 13:46
    if you have a branch with more than two
    branches. So, you can cover a lot of
  • 13:46 - 13:51
    arguments using these kinds of diagrams.
    The method can be described in general,
  • 13:51 - 13:55
    like this. You start by identifying the
    premises and the conclusions, and you
  • 13:55 - 14:00
    number them. So that you can just have
    numbers instead of having to write out the
  • 14:00 - 14:04
    whole sentence on the diagram. Then, when
    they work together, you put a plus sign
  • 14:04 - 14:09
    between them and draw a line under it to
    indicate that they're working together.
  • 14:09 - 14:15
    They're functioning as a group. Then, you
    draw an arrow from the claims that are
  • 14:15 - 14:20
    reasons to the claims that they are
    reasons for. And then, you move them
  • 14:20 - 14:25
    around on the diagram so that they'll form
    a line when it's a linear structure and
  • 14:25 - 14:30
    branches when it's a branching structure.
    But, it will be easy to rearrange them so
  • 14:30 - 14:35
    as to show how all of the different
    premises and conclusions work together in
  • 14:35 - 14:40
    a single argumentative structure. That's
    going to be enough to accomplish this
  • 14:40 - 14:46
    stage of reconstruction. Namely, to
    organize the parts and show how they work
  • 14:46 - 14:49
    together in the overall argument.
Title:
Lecture 3-5 - Organize Parts
jngiam edited English subtitles for Lecture 3-5 - Organize Parts
jngiam added a translation

English subtitles

Revisions