Return to Video

Lecture 3-3 - Get Down to Basics

  • 0:03 - 0:07
    Now that we understand validity, we can
    use the notion of validity in
  • 0:07 - 0:12
    reconstructing arguments. Now, the point
    of reconstructing an argument is to put it
  • 0:12 - 0:17
    in a shape that makes it easier for us to
    assess the argument more accurately and
  • 0:17 - 0:22
    fairly for whether it's a good argument or
    a bad argument. And when we do the
  • 0:22 - 0:27
    reconstruction, remember, you want to make
    it as good an argument as possible because
  • 0:27 - 0:31
    you don't learn anything from putting down
    your enemies by making them look silly,
  • 0:31 - 0:36
    right? If you want to learn from somebody
    else's argument, you need to put it in the
  • 0:36 - 0:40
    best shape you can to make it look as good
    as possible. So, that's going to be the
  • 0:40 - 0:45
    goal of reconstruction. And we are going
    to accomplish that goal in a series of
  • 0:45 - 0:51
    stages. The first stage simply to do a
    close analysis and we talked about that
  • 0:51 - 0:56
    last week. The second stage is to get down
    to basics. That is to remove all the
  • 0:56 - 1:00
    excess words and focus on the premises and
    conclusions that really make up the
  • 1:00 - 1:06
    argument and then put those into standard
    form. The third stage is to clarify those
  • 1:06 - 1:10
    premises. They're not always going to be
    as clear as you like and that's going to
  • 1:10 - 1:15
    take some work and it's going to include
    breaking them into parts. And then, the
  • 1:15 - 1:19
    next stage is to take those parts and
    organize them, to put them in order, so
  • 1:19 - 1:24
    you can see how the argument flows from
    one part to another. But not all arguments
  • 1:24 - 1:30
    are complete so the next stage, we have to
    fill in the gaps, that is supply
  • 1:30 - 1:35
    suppressed premises. And once we've done
    that, then the final stage is going to be
  • 1:35 - 1:39
    assess the argument. If we are able to
    come up with a sound reconstruction, we
  • 1:39 - 1:44
    know that the conclusion has to be true.
    Because as we learned in the previous
  • 1:44 - 1:49
    lecture, the conclusion of sound arguments
    is always true. But if we don't come up
  • 1:49 - 1:53
    with a sound reconstruction, then we've
    got to decide, is it the fault of the
  • 1:53 - 1:58
    argument or is it our own fault because we
    didn't come up with a sound reconstruction
  • 1:58 - 2:02
    when there really is one that we didn't
    find. So, that's going to be something we
  • 2:02 - 2:06
    have to discuss. We're g oing to discuss
    all of these stages over the next few
  • 2:06 - 2:10
    lectures. Now, the first stage of
    reconstruction is to do a close analysis.
  • 2:10 - 2:15
    But we already learned how to do that,
    that was easy. Boy, I hope the rest of
  • 2:15 - 2:21
    them are that easy. This lecture is mainly
    going to be about the second stage, namely
  • 2:21 - 2:26
    getting down to basics. And what we want
    to do is to pull out the explicit premise
  • 2:26 - 2:32
    and conclusion from all the other words
    around it. And the first step is to remove
  • 2:32 - 2:37
    all the excess verbiage. You know, it
    might seem very surprising but people
  • 2:37 - 2:42
    often repeat themselves, I'm sure you've
    all run into it. I mean, you listen to
  • 2:42 - 2:47
    somebody give a, a talk and it takes them
    fifty minutes to say what they could have
  • 2:47 - 2:53
    said easily in five minutes and one of the
    reasons is that they say everything ten
  • 2:53 - 2:57
    times. You know, for instance, people
    often say the same thing twice, they
  • 2:57 - 3:02
    repeat themselves. They say the same thing
    over again and they restate the point in
  • 3:02 - 3:07
    different words and they utter sentences
    that mean the same thing. And they say
  • 3:07 - 3:12
    something and then, you know, they say it
    again and they make a claim twice or more.
  • 3:12 - 3:17
    They exert exactly what they just said and
    they reformulate their claim in different
  • 3:17 - 3:22
    words that are equivalent. They say it
    once and then, they say it again, you get
  • 3:22 - 3:28
    the idea. Now, here is a real example from
    a US politician during a debate. I'm going
  • 3:27 - 3:34
    to be honest with people, we can't
    eliminate this deficit. People have heard
  • 3:34 - 3:42
    that over and over again in four years, we
    cannot do it, we're in too deep a hole.
  • 3:43 - 3:49
    Now, if you think about it, it's going to
    be obvious that we cannot do it. Repeats,
  • 3:49 - 3:55
    we can't eliminate this deficit, cuz
    that's what it's doing, it is eliminating
  • 3:55 - 4:01
    the deficit. But also, we're in too deep a
    hole. Well, that's just a metaphorical way
  • 4:01 - 4:06
    of saying the same thing. Why is the hole
    too deep? Because we can't get out of it.
  • 4:06 - 4:11
    What hole is it? It's the deficit hole.
    So, to say we can't get out of this hole,
  • 4:11 - 4:15
    we're in too deep a hole. It's just
    another way of saying we can't eliminate
  • 4:15 - 4:20
    the deficit. So, in these three lin es,
    he's already repeated himself three times.
  • 4:20 - 4:25
    Now, why does this politician repeat
    himself? It might be that he thinks people
  • 4:25 - 4:29
    will remember it better or one version
    will make more sense than another. But he
  • 4:29 - 4:34
    might have a special reason cuz this was a
    live debate and he had to give a 90-second
  • 4:34 - 4:39
    answer. So, he had to fill up the time.
    Sometimes people repeat themselves just to
  • 4:39 - 4:44
    fill up the time or maybe to give himself
    time to think cuz he didn't have a real
  • 4:44 - 4:48
    answer ready yet and repeating himself is
    easy while he thinks about what he's
  • 4:48 - 4:53
    really going to say in the next few
    sentences. Fine. But repeating it still
  • 4:53 - 4:58
    doesn't make the argument any better and
    we want to get down to the basics of the
  • 4:58 - 5:04
    argument that is the parts of the argument
    that really affect how good it is, so we
  • 5:04 - 5:10
    can cross out those repetitions that don't
    make the argument any better. So first, we
  • 5:10 - 5:15
    can cross out we cannot do it. Then, we
    can cross out, we're in too deep a hole.
  • 5:15 - 5:20
    We already saw that those are just
    repeating the claim that we can't
  • 5:20 - 5:26
    eliminate the deficit. In addition, we can
    cross out, I want to be honest with people
  • 5:26 - 5:32
    because that's not a reason to believe
    we're in too deep a deficit. And next, we
  • 5:32 - 5:38
    can cross out that people have heard that
    over and over again in four years. Well,
  • 5:38 - 5:44
    that might be seen as a reason to believe
    that we're in a deficit because everybody
  • 5:44 - 5:50
    seems to say it, but let's assume that's
    not part of his argument here and we'll
  • 5:50 - 5:56
    cross it out. Now, let's move on. A second
    form of excess verbiage that is words that
  • 5:56 - 6:01
    don't contribute to the force of the
    argument is what I like to call road
  • 6:01 - 6:06
    markers. A lot of times, people, you know,
    good speakers, they tell you what topic
  • 6:06 - 6:11
    they are talking about and why they are
    talking about it. Why it's important and
  • 6:11 - 6:16
    worth talking about. But to say why it's
    an important issue and to say what issue
  • 6:16 - 6:21
    it is, doesn't provide any reason to
    believe that what they say about the issue
  • 6:21 - 6:26
    is true or false. So, it doesn't
    contribute to the argument. Here's an
  • 6:26 - 6:31
    example from the same politician in the
    same debate as we j ust saw. This
  • 6:31 - 6:37
    politician said, now, I want to go back to
    the whole issue of healthcare, because we
  • 6:37 - 6:43
    touched it, and I think the American
    people deserve to know what we would do
  • 6:43 - 6:48
    different. And notice that he says, he's
    going to talk about healthcare but he
  • 6:48 - 6:53
    doesn't say anything about healthcare. He
    didn't tell you what he's going to say
  • 6:53 - 6:58
    about healthcare. All he says is he wants
    to go back to that issue. And he tells you
  • 6:58 - 7:04
    why he wants to go back to that issue. But
    he doesn't add any reason to believe that
  • 7:04 - 7:08
    what he's about to say about the issue is
    true. Now, this can, of course, still be
  • 7:08 - 7:13
    useful because you might get confused
    about what the issue is and he might be
  • 7:13 - 7:18
    changing the topic and he wants to signal
    that he is changing the topic, and that
  • 7:17 - 7:22
    will help his listeners. But it still
    doesn't add to the argument, it doesn't
  • 7:22 - 7:27
    give you any reason for the conclusion
    that he's going to want to draw. We can
  • 7:27 - 7:31
    cross out these excess words. we can cross
    out, now, I want to go back to the whole
  • 7:31 - 7:36
    issue of healthcare because that doesn't
    show that his views on healthcare are
  • 7:36 - 7:40
    correct. And we can cross out because we
    touched it. That's a reason why we're
  • 7:40 - 7:45
    going to that issue, but again, that
    doesn't give any reason why his views are
  • 7:45 - 7:49
    correct. And we can even cross out, but I
    think the American people deserve to know
  • 7:49 - 7:54
    what we would do different because the
    fact that they deserve to know what you're
  • 7:54 - 7:58
    going to do doesn't show that what you're
    going to do is the right thing to do. So,
  • 7:58 - 8:03
    none of these claims are really reasons
    that are going to be reasons for the main
  • 8:03 - 8:07
    part of his argument, which is to support
    the particular views on healthcare that
  • 8:07 - 8:12
    he's going to tell you about a few seconds
    after this. The next type of excess
  • 8:12 - 8:19
    verbiage is tangents. People go off on
    tangents all the time. Here's an example.
  • 8:20 - 8:24
    You know, you really ought to think about
    taking a History course. I, I still
  • 8:24 - 8:29
    remember my History courses in college.
    There was this one time when, there was a
  • 8:29 - 8:34
    dog that one of the students brought to
    class and, and the dog like barked and
  • 8:34 - 8:39
    then he ran up on stage and he, he cut
    under the professor and knocked the
  • 8:39 - 8:44
    professor on his rear-end. It was really
    funny. So, you know, I think that History
  • 8:44 - 8:49
    is a good thing to study. Now, notice that
    all this stuff about the dog has nothing
  • 8:49 - 8:54
    to do with History. It's no reason to take
    a History course instead of a Philosophy
  • 8:54 - 8:59
    course or a Classics course or a Science
    course. The same thing could happen in
  • 8:59 - 9:04
    those courses just as well. So, the
    tangent plays a certain role. It makes it
  • 9:04 - 9:09
    interesting. It keeps your attention.
    Maybe it makes it memorable for you, what
  • 9:09 - 9:14
    he said. But it doesn't actually provide a
    reason why you ought to take a History
  • 9:14 - 9:20
    course. So, since those parts of the words
    were just a tangent that don't provide any
  • 9:20 - 9:27
    reason we can cross them out, too, because
    they are excess verbiage. But sometimes,
  • 9:27 - 9:32
    people go off on irrelevant tangents. Not
    just by accident because they lose their
  • 9:32 - 9:37
    train of thought, but because they're
    trying to fool you. They're trying to
  • 9:37 - 9:43
    produce what is called a red herring. The
    name red hearing supposedly comes from
  • 9:43 - 9:48
    somebody who crossed the red herring over
    the trail and then the hound couldn't
  • 9:48 - 9:53
    track its scent anymore. And that's
    basically what's going on here. Sometimes,
  • 9:53 - 9:59
    people produce tangents that distracts you
    from the main line of argument because
  • 9:59 - 10:04
    they know that there are weaknesses in
    that line of argument and they don't want
  • 10:04 - 10:09
    you to notice them. That's what a red
    herring is. And it's a type of tangent
  • 10:09 - 10:14
    that you have to learn to watch out for.
    Because if you want to see the problems in
  • 10:14 - 10:20
    your opponent's arguments or even in your
    friend's arguments, then you need to not
  • 10:20 - 10:26
    get distracted by tangents that are in
    effect red herrings. Yet, another example
  • 10:26 - 10:34
    of excess verbiage is, well, examples.
    Here's an example of that. A different
  • 10:34 - 10:40
    politician in the same debate said this.
    Here's what happened. In the time that
  • 10:40 - 10:47
    they have been in office in the last four
    years, 1.6 million private sector jobs
  • 10:47 - 10:54
    have been lost, 2.7 million manufacturing
    jobs have been lost. And it's had real
  • 10:54 - 10:59
    consequences in places like Cle veland.
    Cleveland is a wonderful distinguished
  • 10:59 - 11:05
    city. It's done a lot of great things, but
    it has the highest poverty rate in the
  • 11:05 - 11:12
    country. One out of almost two children in
    Cleveland are now living in poverty. Now,
  • 11:12 - 11:18
    notice that this politician is talking
    about the unemployment rate in the rest of
  • 11:18 - 11:24
    the country, in the country as a whole.
    So, why bring in Cleveland? Well, you
  • 11:24 - 11:28
    might be saying that Cleveland shows that
    there's problems throughout the rest of
  • 11:28 - 11:33
    the country, but that can't be right
    because Cleveland is just one example. And
  • 11:33 - 11:37
    it might be an outlier that doesn't
    represent the general trends. So, what
  • 11:37 - 11:42
    he's doing with this example is he's
    trying to bring it down the home, and make
  • 11:42 - 11:46
    you feel for the real effects. But he
    doesn't come out and say that you can
  • 11:46 - 11:51
    generalize from Cleveland to the rest of
    the country, or that everyone else is
  • 11:51 - 11:55
    suffering in exactly the same way. He's
    just giving one example. And so, it
  • 11:55 - 12:00
    doesn't really support his general claim
    that the unemployment is a problem
  • 12:00 - 12:06
    throughout the whole country. That means
    that it's not an extra premise in the
  • 12:06 - 12:13
    argument and we can cross it out like
    other forms of excess verbiage. Now, we've
  • 12:13 - 12:19
    seen that excess verbiage can take the
    form of repetition or road markers or
  • 12:19 - 12:26
    tangents or examples. And people use these
    a lot. Matter of fact, I like to think of
  • 12:26 - 12:32
    a general trick that people use called the
    trick of excess verbiage. A lot of people
  • 12:32 - 12:38
    talk too much and they keep saying things
    over and over again, go off on tangents,
  • 12:38 - 12:44
    and give more examples than they really
    need. And all of that is a way of hiding
  • 12:44 - 12:49
    the problem with their position. It's a
    trick to use too many words because the
  • 12:49 - 12:55
    real point gets lost in the middle of
    those words. So, you can fool people by
  • 12:55 - 13:02
    throwing in those extra words. That's the
    trick of excess verbiage but be careful.
  • 13:02 - 13:08
    What seems like excess verbiage that's
    just there to trick you might really be an
  • 13:08 - 13:13
    essential part of the argument. So what
    you need to do when you have a passage and
  • 13:13 - 13:17
    you're trying to get the argument out of
    it, is to cross out all the exc ess words
  • 13:17 - 13:22
    but also look at what's left over. If
    what's left over is enough premises and
  • 13:22 - 13:27
    conclusion to make a good argument, then
    the stuff that you crossed out probably
  • 13:27 - 13:32
    really is excess. But if it turns out that
    what's left over is not a very good
  • 13:32 - 13:37
    argument, to autocheck all those words you
    crossed out and make sure they really
  • 13:37 - 13:41
    weren't necessary. Cuz you're not being
    fair to the person that you're
  • 13:41 - 13:46
    interpreting if you crossed out something
    that was an essential part of the
  • 13:46 - 13:52
    argument. And some cases are going to be
    tricky. Its not going to be clear whether
  • 13:52 - 13:58
    or not to cross the noun. Some small words
    that are tricky are guarding terms. Here
  • 13:58 - 14:03
    is an example. I think Miranda is at home
    so we can meet her there. What's the
  • 14:03 - 14:09
    guarding word? You already found that out
    when you did the close analysis, right? I
  • 14:09 - 14:16
    think. Now, one way to read this argument
    is that the premises I think Miranda is at
  • 14:16 - 14:21
    home and the conclusion is we can meet her
    there. But that's kind of weird because
  • 14:21 - 14:25
    the fact that you think she is at home is
    not what makes it true that you can meet
  • 14:25 - 14:29
    her there, it's the fact that she is at
    home that can make it the case that you
  • 14:29 - 14:33
    can meet her there. So, if the premise is
    about what you think, and the conclusion
  • 14:33 - 14:37
    is about where she is and where you can
    meet her, then the argument doesn't make
  • 14:37 - 14:42
    any sense. So, in this case, what we want
    to do is to cross out the words I think,
  • 14:42 - 14:47
    because that's going to make the argument
    silly and the argument really amounts to,
  • 14:47 - 14:52
    Miranda is at home, so we can meet her
    there. And the I think covers that whole
  • 14:52 - 14:57
    thing. It's saying, I think she's at home,
    so I think we can meet her there. But the
  • 14:57 - 15:03
    argument doesn't involve some premise
    about what your thoughts are and contrast
  • 15:03 - 15:09
    this with a different argument. Miranda is
    at home, so we can probably meet her
  • 15:09 - 15:15
    there. Now, there's another guarding term,
    right? Probably. Can you get rid of that?
  • 15:15 - 15:20
    Well, then the argument becomes Miranda is
    at home, so we can meet her there. But
  • 15:20 - 15:25
    that's clearly not what the speaker was
    trying to say, if they included the word
  • 15:25 - 15:27
    probab ly.
    They realized that the fact that she's at
  • 15:27 - 15:32
    home right now doesn't mean that we can
    meet her there because it might take us
  • 15:32 - 15:36
    awhile to get there and she might leave
    while we're on the way. So, it's not fair
  • 15:36 - 15:41
    to the person giving the argument. And it
    makes the argument look worse to cross out
  • 15:41 - 15:46
    the word, probably. So, in that case, you
    want to keep the guarding term in order to
  • 15:46 - 15:51
    properly represent the force of the
    argument. So, it looks like sometimes, you
  • 15:51 - 15:56
    need to keep the guarding terms and
    sometimes, you need to cross them out. And
  • 15:56 - 16:01
    there's not going to be any strict rule
    that you can follow. You have to use your
  • 16:01 - 16:06
    sense of what's going to make the argument
    as good as possible. What's going to fit
  • 16:06 - 16:12
    what the speaker was really trying to say.
    Another tricky case is assuring terms.
  • 16:12 - 16:17
    Suppose I'm writing a letter of
    recommendation and I say, he is clearly a
  • 16:17 - 16:25
    great worker. I know that. So, you ought
    to hire him. The assuring terms are
  • 16:25 - 16:32
    clearly and I know that. But now, the
    question is, is the argument really first
  • 16:32 - 16:37
    premise, he's clearly a great worker.
    Second premise, I know that. Conclusion,
  • 16:37 - 16:42
    you ought to hire him. It's kind of weird.
    Again, if you think about it, cuz you're
  • 16:42 - 16:47
    not hiring him because it's clear. If he's
    a great worker but it's not clear that
  • 16:47 - 16:51
    he's a great worker, then you're still
    ought to hire him because he is a great
  • 16:51 - 16:56
    worker. Or if he's a great worker and I
    don't know he's a great worker, you still
  • 16:56 - 17:00
    ought to hire him cuz he's a great worker.
    The fact that I know it is irrelevant to
  • 17:00 - 17:05
    whether you want to hire him cuz that's
    about my mental states not his abilities.
  • 17:05 - 17:09
    So, that representation of the argument
    doesn't really capture the force of
  • 17:09 - 17:14
    somebody who writes this letter of
    recommendation. So, we can cross out the
  • 17:14 - 17:20
    words I know that and we can cross out
    clearly, and then the argument is he's a
  • 17:20 - 17:27
    great worker so you ought to hire him. But
    contrast this example. I am certain that
  • 17:27 - 17:34
    Jacob is cheating on his wife, so I ougt
    to tell her. Now, you might think I am
  • 17:34 - 17:38
    certain that is just another assuring term
    so we can cross it ou t.
  • 17:38 - 17:43
    And then, the real argument is Jacob is
    cheating on his wife so I ought to tell
  • 17:43 - 17:49
    her. But now, think about that argument.
    The mere fact that he's cheating on his
  • 17:49 - 17:53
    wife doesn't mean I ought to tell her if
    I'm not certain cuz if I have some
  • 17:53 - 17:58
    suspicions or I'm just guessing, but I
    really don't know, then I probably ought
  • 17:58 - 18:03
    not to tell Jacob's wife that, you know,
    Jacob was cheating on her. So here, the
  • 18:03 - 18:09
    force of the argument, does seem to depend
    on my certainty. If I'm not certain, I
  • 18:09 - 18:14
    shouldn't tell her. If I am certain, maybe
    I should. So, we can't cross out the
  • 18:14 - 18:19
    assuring term in this case cuz that would
    distort the argument. And, of course, some
  • 18:19 - 18:23
    people might disagree with that. They
    might say, well, look, if you have some
  • 18:23 - 18:27
    reason but your not certain then you ought
    to tell her and that could be
  • 18:27 - 18:32
    controversial. But we're talking here not
    about what those people think but what the
  • 18:32 - 18:37
    speaker thinks, the person giving this
    argument when this person said,"I'm I'm
  • 18:37 - 18:42
    certain that Jacob is cheating on his
    wife." They seemed to indicate that to
  • 18:42 - 18:46
    them, the fact that they are certain
    provides an even better reason why he
  • 18:46 - 18:52
    should tell Jacob's wife. So, if we want
    to capture what the person giving the
  • 18:52 - 18:57
    argument intended in this case, we have to
    leave them the assuring term. So, you're
  • 18:57 - 19:01
    seeing one example, where you ought to get
    rid of the assuring terms. And another
  • 19:01 - 19:06
    example, where you ought to keep the
    reassuring terms. And just like with
  • 19:06 - 19:11
    guarding terms the same point applies.
    There is no mechanic rule that will apply
  • 19:11 - 19:16
    to every case. You have to think through
    the argument and decide whether crossing
  • 19:16 - 19:22
    out those words and removing them distorts
    the argument or instead, crossing them out
  • 19:22 - 19:26
    makes the argument look even better
    because the point of removing excess
  • 19:26 - 19:32
    verbiage is to get rid of the things that
    aren't necessary but keep everything that
  • 19:32 - 19:38
    is necessary to make the argument look as
    good as it possibly can look. Finally,
  • 19:38 - 19:43
    once we've removed all the excess
    verbiage, what's left over? The answer is
  • 19:43 - 19:47
    the explicit premises and conclusion in
    the argume nt.
  • 19:47 - 19:52
    The point of removing the excess verbiage
    was to separate those essential parts of
  • 19:52 - 19:58
    the argument, those basics of the argument
    from all the stuff that's unnecessary. Of
  • 19:58 - 20:02
    course, we still have to decide which ones
    are premises and which ones the
  • 20:02 - 20:07
    conclusion, right? And that's why the
    close analysis helps because we indicated
  • 20:07 - 20:11
    which ones were reason markers and which
    ones were conclusion markers and that lets
  • 20:11 - 20:16
    you to identify that these are the
    premises and that's the conclusion. And so
  • 20:16 - 20:20
    now, we can do step three. We can put the
    argument standard form. We put the
  • 20:20 - 20:25
    premises above the line and we put dot
    pyramid, and then the conclusion below the
  • 20:25 - 20:30
    line. And we've got the argument in
    standard form, which completes stage two
  • 20:30 - 20:35
    of the reconstruction project. At this
    point, it's useful to look back at the
  • 20:35 - 20:40
    passage and see whether you've gotten rid
    off all the excess included all of the
  • 20:40 - 20:45
    basics of the argument. So, you can look
    at the passage and say, is everything
  • 20:45 - 20:50
    that's not crossed out in a premise or a
    conclusion of the standard form. And if
  • 20:50 - 20:55
    there's something that's still there in
    the passage that isn't used, you've got to
  • 20:55 - 21:00
    decide at that point is it really excess
    or not. And, of course, if the argument
  • 21:00 - 21:05
    looks really bad, you've got to look back
    and see whether it's missing something
  • 21:05 - 21:09
    that you had crossed out as being excess
    verbiage when it really was an essential
  • 21:09 - 21:14
    part of the argument. So, we can use this
    process of putting it into standard form
  • 21:14 - 21:19
    as a test of whether we've performed
    properly the other step of getting rid of
  • 21:19 - 21:25
    excess verbiage. So, steps two and three
    really work together in this stage two of
  • 21:25 - 21:31
    getting down to basics. That's what helps
    us to use the different parts to see
  • 21:31 - 21:34
    whether we've done each of them properly.
Title:
Lecture 3-3 - Get Down to Basics
jngiam edited English subtitles for Lecture 3-3 - Get Down to Basics
jngiam added a translation

English subtitles

Revisions